Skip to main content
Log in

Libertarianism, Legitimation, and the Problems of Regulating Cognition-Enhancing Drugs

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Neuroethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Some libertarians tend to advocate the wide availability of cognition-enhancing drugs beyond their current prescription-only status. They suggest that certain kinds of drugs can be a component of a prudential conception of the ‘good life’—they enhance our opportunities and preferences; and therefore, if a person freely chooses to use them, then there is no justification for the kind of prejudicial, authoritative restrictions that are currently deployed in public policy. In particular, this libertarian idea signifies that if enhancements are a prudential ‘good’ for the user, then this can also be construed as a moral good for all rational agents. If this argument is successful, there can be no substantial distinction between the categorical benefits of enhancement, and what is labeled as an enhancement technology. In this paper, I argue that the exclusivity of egotistical choice, and an uncritical deployment of enhancement as a prudential good, underplays the role of a social and political community when creating a procedurally just and effective public policy. Principally, the argument is devoid of any ethical system to permit the external—and therefore public–appreciation of the social context of moral decisions. In effect, libertarian arguments of this sort must disregard any ideas of public ethics, because the liberty to use whatever means available to gain a socio-economic advantage actually extinguishes any professed legitimation strategy. Escaping the procedural aspects of public policy, which are considered integral to authoritative coherence, results in the erosion of any moral obligations. Thus, in a libertarian society, disenfranchised individuals—such as those harmed through addiction—are the unlucky or superfluous product of a liberal and ‘progressive’ society.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Enhancment nootropics characteristically improve executive capacities above ‘normal’ in healthy users [1]. They include a growing list of ‘smart drugs’, such as Ritalin, Adderall and Modafinil.

  2. I use the term ‘egoist’ to signify that, for the libertarian, self-interest comes first in deciding upon one’s course of action. Sanders argues that the moral grounding of egoism is problematic, because any other-regarding action, including the minimal condition of avoiding harm to others (discussed below), requires that self-interest is not the only justifying reason to act; and therefore, self-interest cannot be the terminal point of ethical reasoning [2].

  3. In contrast, a recent paper by the American Association of Neurology takes a principalist approach to the use of neuroenhancements [5].

  4. Moral obligations are thereby linked to Mill’s ‘liberty principle’: the justification for pursuing a given action is ‘that the individual is not accountable to society for his actions, in so far as these concern the interests of no person but himself’ [10].

  5. This theoretical insight was developed by myself, with Lisbeth W. Nielsen and Gordon Stirrat. Our thesis is as follows: if enhancement did contain an affirmative subject-predicate judgement, then that quality would be discernable external to all agents’ experiences. But this creates a contradiction: on the one hand, it would be irrational for an agent not to exercise a degree of caution, and even scepticism, as to the benefits that she will accrue or risks she must take on (i.e. that ‘X may be good’). On the other hand, agents would be unable to entertain the choice not to use enhancements, because not to do so would be irrational according to the narrow criterion of ‘good’.

  6. ‘Hobbes here means “the fair and the just”’ [26].

  7. Under the constraints of such a system, we are not allowed to live out all our preferences, because some will be formally designated as illegal. It is a central caveat of an egalitarian system of government that such preferences are judged by fair systems of arbitration, rather than mere preference [39].

References

  1. For a scientific review of nootropics, see: Jones, R., K. Morris, and D. Nutt. 2007. Cognition Enhancers. In Drugs and the future: brain science, addiction and society, eds. D. Nutt, T. Robbins, G. Stimson, M. Ince, A. and Jackson, 241–283. London: Academic Press.

  2. Sanders, S. 1988. Is egoism morally defensible? Philosophia 18: 191–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Parens, E. 1998. Enhancing human traits: Ethical and social implications. Washington: Georgetown University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  4. President’s Council on Bioethics. 2003. Beyond therapy. Biotechnology and the pursuit of happiness. Washington, DC: President’s Council on Bioethics.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Lerriviere, D., M. Williams, M. Rizzo, and R. Bonnie. 2009. Responding to requests from adult patients for neuroenhancements. Neurology 73: 1406–1412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Harris, J. 2005. Enhancements are a moral obligation. WellcomeScience 1: 16–17.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Harris, J., and S. Chan. 2008. Enhancement is good for you!: Understanding the ethics of genetic enhancement. Gene Therapy 15: 338–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Berlin, I. 1969. Four essays on liberty. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Harris, J. 2004. Response to “utilitarianism shot down by its own men” by Tuija Takala (CQ Vol 12, No 4). Takala shoots herself in the foot. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 13: 170–178.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Mill, J. 2003. On liberty. In Utilitarianism and on liberty, ed. M. Warnock, 163. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Locke, J. 1988. Two treatises of government. Student Edition, ed. P. Laslett, 271. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  12. Harris, J. 2007. Enhancing evolution: The ethical case for making better people. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Greely, H., B. Sahakian, J. Harris, R. Kessler, M. Gazzaniga, P. Campbell, and M. Farah. 2008. Towards responsible use of cognitive-enhancing drugs by the healthy. Nature 11: 702–705.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Greyling, A. 2007. The choice of Hercules. London: Weiden & Nicolson.

    Google Scholar 

  15. From: Kramer, P. 1993. Listening to Prozac. New York: Penguin.

  16. Nutt, D., L. King, W. Saulsbury, and C. Blakemore. 2007. Development of a rational scale to assess the harm of drugs of potential misuse. Lancet 369: 1047–1053.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. On this point, see the discussion in: Mackenzie, R. 2006. Addiction in public health and criminal justice system governance: Neuroscience, enhancement and happiness research. Genomics, Society and Policy 2: 92–109.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Cf. President’s Council on Bioethics. 2003. Beyond Therapy: Biotechnology and the Pursuit of Happiness, 138. Washington, DC: President’s Council on Bioethics and Sandel, M. 2004. The case against perfection. The Atlantic, April, 293(3).

  19. See John Harris’ comments, interviewed in: Ahuja, A. 2007. Enhancing the species. The Times 10 October: 4–5.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Lawrence Summers, quoted in: Yergin, D. and J. Stanislaw. 1998. The commanding heights: The battle between government and the marketplace that is remaking the modern world, 150–151. New York: Simon & Schuster.

  21. Hayek, F. 1960. The constiution of liberty, 103. London: Routledge & Keegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Nozick, R. 1974. Anarchy, state and Utopia, 310. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Bentham, J. 1843. Principles of the civil code. In The works of Jeremy Bentham, vol. I, ed. J. Bowering, 321–364. Edinburgh: William Tait. p. 321.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Bentham, J. 1996. An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. eds. J. Burns and H. Hart, with a new introduction by F. Rosen, and an Interpretive Essay by H. Hart. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 12–13.

  25. Bentham, J. 1843. The Book of Political Fallacies: from Unfinished Papers of Jeremy Bentham, Edited by a Friend (orr. publication 1824). In The Works of Jeremy Bentham, Volume II, ed. J. Bowering, 377–487. Edinburgh: William Tait. p. 416.

  26. Reynolds, N., and A. Saxonhouse (eds.). 1997. Three discourses by Thomas Hobbes. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Note by the editors, p. 106.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Hobbes, T. 1997. Three discourses. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Cf. Akerman, B. 1980. Social justice and the liberal state. New Haven, Conn: Yale University Press.

  29. Galligan, D. 2007. Citizens’ rights and participation in the regulation of biotechnology. In Biotechnologies and international human rights, ed. F. Francioni, 335–359. Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Esteban McCabe, S., J. Knight, C. Teter, and H. Wechsler. 2005. Non-medical use of prescription stimulants among US college students: prevalence and correlates from a national survey. Addiction 100: 96–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Maher, B. 2008. Poll results: Look who’s doping. Nature 452: 674–675.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Volkow, N., et al. 2009. Effects of modafinil on dopamine and dopamine transporters in the male human brain. Journal of the American Medical Association 301: 1148–1154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Madras, B., et al. 2006. Modafinil occupies dopamine and norepinephrine transporters in vivo and modulates the transporters and trace amine activity in vitro. Journal of Pharmacology and Experimental Therapeutics 319: 561–569.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Reith, G. 2004. Consumption and its discontents: Addiction, identity and the problems of freedom. British Journal of Sociology 55: 283–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Mackenzie, R. 2006. Addiction in public health and criminal justice system governance: neuroscience, enhancement and happiness research. Genomics, Society and Policy 2: 92–109. p. 96.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Volkow, N., and T.-K. Li. 2005. The neuroscience of addiction. Nature Neuroscience 8: 1429–1430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. McKeganey, N., J. Neale, C. Lloyd, and G. Hay. 2007. Sociology and substance use. In Drugs and the future: Brain science, addiction and society, ed. D. Nutt, T. Robbins, G. Stimson, M. Ince, and A. Jackson, 359–387. London: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Black, J. 2005. What is regulatory innovation? In Regulatory innovation: A comparative analysis, ed. J. Black, M. Lodge, and M. Thatcher, 1–15. Cheltenham: Edwards Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Neal, P. 1985. Liberalism and neutrality. Polity 17: 664–684.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Cf. Gewirth, A. 1986. The community of rights. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

  41. Frankena, W. 1966. The concept of morality. Journal of Philosophy 63: 688–696.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. Ian McEwan, quoted in D. Lodge. 2002. Sense and Sensibility. The Guardian Review, 2 November, 4–6.

  43. Gewirth, A. 1983. The rationality of reasonableness. Synthese 57: 225–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. Gewirth, A. 1978. Reason and morality. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Neuhouser, F. 1993. Freedom, dependence, and the General Will. The Philosophical Review 102: 363–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  46. On a related topic, Holm & McNamee show that the pressures of professional sport can lead to some unwelcome practices and health risks, and ask whether these may be further encouraged by the use of performance enhancements; Holm, S. and M. McNamee. 2009. Ethics in sports medicine: Professional standards need to be clarified and acted on. BMJ 339: 984–985.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Beyleveld, D., and R. Brownsword. 1986. Law as a moral judgment. London: Sweet and Maxwell.

    Google Scholar 

  48. See: Brownsword, R. 2005. Code, control, and choice: Why east is east and west is west. Legal Studies 25: 1–21.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Benjamin Capps.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Capps, B. Libertarianism, Legitimation, and the Problems of Regulating Cognition-Enhancing Drugs. Neuroethics 4, 119–128 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-010-9059-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-010-9059-3

Keywords

Navigation