Skip to main content
Log in

Extended Knowledge-How

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to reductive intellectualists about knowledge-how (e.g. Stanley and Williamson in J Philos 411–44, 2001; Stanley in Know how. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2011; Brogaard in Grazer Philos Stud 77(1):147–190, 2008; Philos Phenomenol Res 78(2):439–467, 2009) knowledge-how is a kind of knowledge-that. To the extent that this is right, then insofar as we might conceive of ways knowledge could be extended with reference to active externalist (e.g. Clark and Chalmers in Analysis 58(1):7–19, 1998; Clark in Supersizing the mind: embodiment, action, and cognitive extension: embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford University Press , Oxford, 2008) approaches in the philosophy of mind (e.g. the extended mind thesis and the hypothesis of extended cognition), we should expect no interesting difference between the two. However, insofar as anti-intellectualist approaches to knowledge-how (e.g. Ryle in Proc Aristot Soc 46, 1945; The concept of mind. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1949) are a viable option, there is an overlooked issue of how knowledge-how might be extended, via active externalism, in ways very differently from knowledge-that. This paper explores this overlooked space, and in doing so, illustrates how a novel form of extended knowledge-how emerges from a pairing of active externalism in the philosophy of mind with anti-intellectualism in the theory of knowledge. Crucial to our argument will be a new way of thinking about the extended mind thesis, as it pertains to the kinds of state one is in (on an anti-intellectualist construal) when one knows how to do something, and how this state connects with non-accidentally successful performance.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This term owes to Clark and Chalmers (1998), who distinguish active externalism from ‘passive externalism’, which they use to characterize the kind of externalism that is implied by the view that mental contents are widely individuated (e.g. Putnam 1975; Burge 1986). For a representative example of some recent defences of active externalist views, see Clark and Chalmers (1998), Clark (2008), Clark (2010), Hutchins (1995), Menary (2006), Palermos (2011), (2014a, b), Theiner et al. (2010), Wilson (2000), (2004).

  2. Put slightly differently, we might also say that different varieties of active externalism map on to different strategies for combating what Clark calls ‘bioprejudice’—viz., when it is just on account of something’s being located outside the skull and skin that it is excluded from cognition. Active externalism is thus egalitarian in its approach to cognitive theorizing.

  3. There is a version of active externalism that is perhaps more radical by the lights of orthodoxy than the extended mind thesis. This is the distributed cognition thesis (e.g. Hutchins 1995). We’ll be setting this view aside for the present purposes.

  4. In fact, the seminal discussion (Clark and Chalmers 1998) is an example of such a running together of EMT and HEC. See Palermos (2014a) for helpful discussion of the differences.

  5. See, along with the bloat objection noted here, Adams and Aizawa’s (2008) objection to the extended mind which draws from a distinction between derived and underived content.

  6. See here Rupert (2004, 401–405) and also Carter et al. (2014).

  7. Clark’s (2010, 46) criteria are that: (1) “That the resource be reliably available and typically invoked.” (2) “That any information thus retrieved be more-or-less automatically endorsed. It should not usually be subject to critical scrutiny. [...] It should be deemed about as trustworthy as something retrieved clearly from biological memory.” (3) “That information contained in the resource should be easily accessible as and when required.”

  8. See Carter (2013), Carter and Palermos (2014), Carter and Kallestrup (2015) and Carter and Pritchard (forthcoming). See also Menary (2006) and Pritchard (2010).

  9. See here, along with Palermos (2011, 2014a, b), Carter et al. (forthcoming), Chemero (2009), Froese et al. (2013), Sutton et al. (2008), Theiner et al. (2010) and Tollefsen and Dale (2011).

  10. Compare the case of Otto, who mutually interacts with his notebook, with ‘one-way’ or non-reciprocal causation, as we might have in an amended case where Otto does not interact himself with the notebook by writing entries in it, but rather, simply relies on an external signal to tell him what to do at each juncture. In a case where Otto simply accepts the instructions of the signaler, the signaler is not (according to DST at least) a part of Otto’s extended cognitive process, as the relevant causal relations are not mutually directed but one-way.

  11. See also Carter (2013), Carter and Palermos (2014), Carter and Kallestrup (2015) and Carter and Pritchard (forthcoming).

  12. See fn. 1. This programme consists of the extended mind, extended cognition and distributed cognition programs. See Pritchard (2010), Palermos (2014a, b) and Carter et al. (2014) for more on this distinction.

  13. Ryle of course took himself to be challenging more generally Descartes’ picture of the mind as a ‘ghost in the machine’ a picture on which action has intelligence properties only when guided by acts of the mind—viz., the consideration of regulatory propositions. However, what matters for the present purposes is that Chapter 2 of The Concept of Mind as well as Ryle’s (1945) Aristotelian Society Address constitute the seminal case for thinking, in particular, that knowing how to do something is grounded in abilities, not (propositional) knowledge, and it is this picture that has been inherited in mainstream epistemology, more or less, until recent challenges by Stanley and Williamson and others on linguistic grounds.

  14. An even more simplified picture of the distinction between intellectualism and anti-intellectualism goes like this: knowing how to do something just is having a certain ability or disposition to do that thing; by contrast, intellectualism claims that knowing how to do something just is a kind of propositional knowledge. While Ryle probably endorsed something like this simplified view of anti-intellectualism and Stanley and Williamson (2001), as well as Stanley (2011) endorse this simplified statement of intellectualism, we have resisted this kind of characterization. This is because, following 1, we think the simplified picture runs together two issues that can come apart. On the one hand, there is the issue of what grounds knowledge how—e.g. what is it in virtue of which one knows how to do something. This is we think the key question separating anti-intellectualist and intellectualists. One says propositional attitudes, the other abilities. A separate matter altogether is what is the metaphysical nature of knowing how to do something: here, for instance, an intellectualist can say that the nature of knowing how to do something is a relation between an agent and a proposition, though this need not be one’s answer to the nature question, simply in virtue of being an intellectualist about what grounds knowledge how. For an example of an intellectualist proposal that is not ‘reductive’ (e.g. which does not simply reduce the nature of knowing how to a propositional attitude relation), see Bengson and Moffett (2011a).

  15. The recent emergence of linguistically-driven intellectualism has led a number of writers to go back and give sustained critiques of Ryle’s original ‘regress’-style arguments for anti-intellectualism about knowledge how. See here, for instance, Bengson and Moffett (2011b).

  16. For some examples of reductive intellectualism, see Stanley and Williamson (2001), Stanley (2011), Brogaard (2008, 2009). Cf. Bengson and Moffett (2011a), Bengson and Moffett (2007) for some examples of non-reductive intellectualism.

  17. This point has been noted by Paul Snowdon (2004).

  18. Recently Carter and Pritchard (2014) have offered a different approach featuring (actual) achievement as candidate for knowledge-how.

  19. For more on this difference see, for example, Stout (2005).

  20. Note that, when EMT is applied to mental states, the claim about propositional knowledge-how is that it may be—among other available options—an appropriately formed true belief with some \(\varphi \)-relevant content. But if in formulating EM*T we attempted to draw on a strict analogy with EMT, we would arrive at the thesis whereby appropriately successful action is extended. Although, actions seem to make good candidates for extension, there is no straightforward way of construing them as mental states. This is why it seems more natural to attend to dispositions.

  21. Note that insofar as this latter formulation is intended as expository rather than motivational, it does not attain the status of a principle. EM*T, as we envisage it here, is motivated by Epistemic Parity Principle for States of Knowledge-How. Granting that Epistemic Parity Principle for States of Knowledge-How holds, it simply entails the parity of exercises.

  22. This is because, one is in a position to speak about extended knowledge how in those cases where it is not exercised. We will not rehearse examples to this effect here.

  23. Earlier we have mentioned hybridization of categorical base. Nonetheless, in cases such as Jens’s it is easy to imagine that continuous advancements in the stem cell research will facilitate the production of medium wavelength cones.

  24. By which we mean the range of colours available to an agent with normally functioning visual system.

  25. Thanks to Duncan Pritchard and Orestis Palermos for helpful discussion. This article was written as part of the AHRC-funded ‘Extended Knowledge’ (AH/J011908/1) research project that is hosted by the University of Edinburgh’s Eidyn research centre. Bolesław Czarnecki’s research was supported by the Polish Ministry of Science and Higher Education, Mobility Plus III research grant (1112/MOB/2013/0).

References

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The bounds of cognition. New Jersey: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen-Hermanson, S. (2013). Superdupersizing the mind: Extended cognition and the persistence of cognitive bloat. Philosophical studies, 164(3), 791–806.

  • Bengson, J., & Moffett, M. (2007). Know-how and concept possession. Philosophical Studies, 136(1), 31–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bengson, J., & Moffett, M. (2011a). Nonpropositional intellectualism. In Knowing how: Essays on knowledge, mind, and action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Bengson, J., & Moffett, M. (2011b). Two conceptions of mind and action: Knowing how and the philosophical theory of intelligence. Knowing how: Essays on knowledge, mind, and action (pp. 3–55). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2008). Knowledge-the and propositional attitude ascriptions. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 77(1), 147–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2009). What Mary Did yesterday: Reflections on knowledge-wh. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 78(2), 439–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2014). A partial defense of extended knowledge. Philosophical Issues, 24(1), 39–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1986). Individualism and psychology. Philosophical Review, 95, 3–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carter, J. A. (2013). Extended cognition and epistemic luck. Synthese, 190(18), 4201–4214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carter, J. A., Gordon, E. C., & Palermos, S. O. (forthcoming). Extended emotion. Philosophical Psychology, 1–24.

  • Carter, J. A. & Kallestrup, J. (2015). Extended cognition and propositional memory. Philosophy and Phenomenolgogical Research. doi:10.1111/phpr.12157.

  • Carter, J. A. & Palermos, S. O. (2014). Active externalism and epistemic internalism. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-014-9670-5.

  • Carter, J. A. & Pritchard, D. (forthcoming). Extended entitlement. In P. Graham & N. Pedersen (Eds.), New essays on entitlement (pp. 1–19). Oxford: UP.

  • Carter, J. A., Kallestrup, J., Palermos, S. O., & Pritchard, D. (2014). Varieties of externalism. Philosophical Issues, 24(1), 63–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carter, J. A. & Pritchard, D. (2014). Knowledge-how and cognitive achievement. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. doi:10.1111/phpr.12094.

  • Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension—Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2010). Memento's revenge: The extended mind, Extended. In R. Menary (Ed.), The Extended Mind (pp. 43–66). Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farkas, K. (forthcoming). Know-wh does not reduce to know-that. American Philosophical Quarterly, 1–18.

  • Froese, T., Gershenson, C., & Rosenblueth, D.A. (2013). The dynamically extended mind. In Evolutionary computation (CEC), 2013 IEEE Congress on, pp. 1419–1426. IEEE, 2013.

  • Hetherington, S. (2013). Knowledge can be lucky. In M. Steup, J. Turri & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology (pp. 164–177). Wiley.

  • Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jarvis, B. (2013). Knowledge, cognitive achievement, and environmental luck. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 94(4), 529–551.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jarvis, B. (forthcoming). Epistemology and radically extended cognition. Episteme, 1–29.

  • Menary, R. (2006). Attacking the bounds of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 19(3), 329–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2012). Cognitive practices and cognitive character. Philosophical Explorations, 15(2), 147–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myers-Schulz, B., & Schwitzgebel, E. (2013). Knowing that P without believing that P. Noûs, 47(2), 371–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palermos, S. O. (2011). Belief-forming processes, extended. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2(4), 741–765.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palermos, S. O. (2014a). Knowledge and cognitive integration. Synthese, 191(8), 1931–1951.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palermos, S. O. (2014b). Loops, constitution, and cognitive extension. Cognitive Systems Research, 27, 25–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2010). Cognitive ability and the extended cognition thesis. Synthese, 175(1), 133–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. & Lynch, M. (forthcoming). Neuromedia. In J. A. Carter, A. Clark, J. Kallestrup, S. O. Palermos & D. Pritchard (Eds.), Extended Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of ‘meaning’. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 7, 131–193.

  • Rupert, R. D. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. The Journal of Philosophy, 101, 389–428.

  • Ryle, G. (1945). Knowing how and knowing that. Proceedings from the Aristotelian Society, 46, 1–16.

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Snowdon, P. (2004). The Presidential address: Knowing how and knowing that: A distinction reconsidered. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 104, 1–29.

  • Stanley, J. (2011). Know how. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2001). Knowing how. The Journal of Philosophy, 98(8), 411–44.

  • Stout, R. (2005). Action. Chesham: Acumen Publishing Limited.

  • Theiner, G., Allen, C., & Goldstone, R. L. (2010). Recognizing group cognition. Cognitive Systems Research, 11(4), 95–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tollefsen, D., & Dale, R. (2011). Naturalizing joint action: A process-based approach. Philosophical Psychology, 25, 385–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A. (2000). The mind beyond itself. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A. (2004). Boundaries of the mind: The Individual in the fragile sciences-cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to J. Adam Carter.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Carter, J.A., Czarnecki, B. Extended Knowledge-How. Erkenn 81, 259–273 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-015-9738-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-015-9738-x

Keywords

Navigation