Skip to main content

Approaching the Truth via Belief Change in Propositional Languages

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
EPSA Epistemology and Methodology of Science

Abstract

Starting from the 1960s of the past century theory change has become a main concern of philosophy of science. Two of the best known formal accounts of theory change are the post-Popperian theories of verisimilitude (PPV for short) and the AGM theory of belief change (AGM for short). In this paper, we will investigate the conceptual relations between PPV and AGM and, in particular, we will ask whether the AGM rules for theory change are effective means for approaching the truth, i.e., for achieving the cognitive aim of science pointed out by PPV. First, the key ideas of PPV and AGM and their application to a particular kind of propositional theories – the so called “conjunctive propositions” – will be illustrated. Afterwards, we will prove that, as far as conjunctive propositions are concerned, AGM belief change is an effective tool for approaching the truth.

Although we are separately responsible for particular sections (Gustavo Cevolani: Sections 5.1.2, 5.2 and 5.3; Francesco Calandra: Section 5.1.1), we have each benefited from regular discussions and the rereading of each other’s contributions, which produced a unified exposition of all the subjects dealt with in the paper.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For a discussion of the problem of rational theory change and its relations with the aims of science, see Cevolani and Festa (2009).

  2. 2.

    In the present paper, the terms “verisimilitude” and “truth approximation” are used as synonymous. The first full-fledged account of verisimilitude was provided by Karl Popper (1963, 1972). Later, David Miller (1974) and Pavel Tichý (1974) showed that Popper’s account was untenable, thus opening the way to the post-Popperian theories of verisimilitude, emerged since 1975. An excellent survey of the modern history of verisimilitude is provided by Niiniluoto (1998).

  3. 3.

    In the literature, the terms “belief dynamics”, “belief change”, and “belief revision” are used as synonymous. AGM, which is named after Alchourrón, Gärdenfors, and Makinson (1985), was developed, starting from the 1970s, by researchers in philosophy of science, logic and Artificial Intelligence. The first monograph devoted to AGM was written by Gärdenfors (1988), and the first textbook presentation by Hansson (1999).

  4. 4.

    Quite recently, however, some AGM theorists have criticized the lack of any concern for truth in AGM. For instance, Hans Rott argues that AGM “should worry more about truth” considered as one of the basic aims of scientific inquiry (see Rott 2000, pp 513, 518 and ff., and in particular note 38).

  5. 5.

    Distance \({\Delta }_{\mathit{ms}}^{\gamma {\gamma }^{{\prime}} }\) is a weighted sum of two simpler (extended) distances, the minimum distance Δmin(T, C i ) and the normalized sum distance Δ sum (T, C i ). The minimum distance of T from C i is the distance from C i of the closest constituent entailing T, defined as: Δmin(T, C i ) = min j{ T} Δ ij . The normalized sum distance of T from C i is the sum of the distances from C i of all the constituents entailing Tnormalized with respect to the sum of the distances of all the elements of C from \({C}_{i} :\ {\Delta }_{\mathit{sum}}(T,{C}_{i}) = \sum_{j\in {\bf T}}{\Delta }_{\mathit{ij}}/\sum_{{C}_{ j}\in {\bf C}}{\Delta }_{\mathit{ij}}\).

  6. 6.

    There are good reasons to think that any plausible measure of verisimilitude should respect (Vs.1–Vs.3) (see Niiniluoto 1987, pp 232–233).

  7. 7.

    The c-version of the similarity approach presented here has been developed by Festa (2007a,b,c), Cevolani and Festa (2009), and Cevolani et al. (2009) with respect to first-order and propositional languages.

  8. 8.

    C-propositions are essentially identical to “descriptive statements” or “D-statements” (Kuipers 1982, pp 348–349) and to “quasi-constituents” (Oddie 1986, p 86).

  9. 9.

    A similar definition can be given with respect to any verisimilitude measure Vs, by selecting a suitable threshold value σ and calling “verisimilar” and “t-distant” those sentences whose verisimilitude is greater or lower than σ, respectively.

  10. 10.

    See Cevolani et al. (forthcoming) for a discussion of contraction.

  11. 11.

    See Niiniluoto (1999), pp 7–9.

  12. 12.

    If T is the theory of an agent X, then T + , T , and T ? can be seen as the set of the b-propositions which Xaccepts, rejects, and on which suspends the judgment, respectively.

  13. 13.

    These theorems are proved in Cevolani et al. (forthcoming) together with a number of results about contraction.

  14. 14.

    The problem of the effectiveness of contraction for approaching the truth is considered in Cevolani et al. (forthcoming).

  15. 15.

    See Niiniluoto (1999), Eq. 5.10.

  16. 16.

    One of the few verisimilitude measures violating (Vs.1) has been proposed by Graham Oddie (1986).

  17. 17.

    See Niiniluoto (1999), pp. 10–13, in particular equations 10, 17 and 20.

  18. 18.

    The proviso is needed in order to exclude the trivial case where A is already contained in T, i.e., the case where A xT = T and \({T}_{A}^{+} = T\).

References

  • Alchourrón C, Gärdenfors P, Makinson D (1985) On the logic of theory change: partial meet contraction and revision functions. J Symbol Logic 50:510–530

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cevolani G, Festa R (2009) Scientific change, belief dynamics and truth approximation. La Nuova Critica 51–52:27–59

    Google Scholar 

  • Cevolani G, Crupi V, Festa R (2009) The whole truth about Linda: probability, verisimilitude and a paradox of conjunction. In: D’Agostino M, Sinigaglia C (eds) Selected papers from the SILFS07 Conference, College Publications, London, forthcoming

    Google Scholar 

  • Cevolani G, Crupi V, Festa R (forthcoming) Verisimilitude and belief change for conjunctive theories

    Google Scholar 

  • Festa R (2007a) The qualitative and statistical verisimilitude of qualitative theories. La Nuova Critica 47–48:91–114

    Google Scholar 

  • Festa R (2007b) Verisimilitude, cross classification, and prediction logic. Approaching the statistical truth by falsified qualitative theories. Mind Soc 6:37–62

    Google Scholar 

  • Festa R (2007c) Verisimilitude, qualitative theories, and statistical inferences. In: Pihlström S, Sintonen M, Raatikainen P (eds) Approaching truth: essays in honour of Ilkka Niiniluoto. College Publications, London, pp 143–177

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors P (1988) Knowledge in flux: modeling the dynamics of epistemic states. MIT Press/Bradford Book, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors P, Makinson D (1988) Revisions of knowledge systems using epistemic entrenchment. In: Vardi MY (ed) Proceedings of the second conference on theoretical aspects of reasoning about knowledge. Morgan Kaufmann, Los Altos, CA, pp 83–95

    Google Scholar 

  • Grove A (1988) Two modelling for theory change. J Philos Logic 17:157–170

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson SO (1999) A textbook of belief dynamics: theory change and database updating. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuipers TAF (1982) Approaching descriptive and theoretical truth. Erkenntnis 18:343–378

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller D (1974) Popper’s qualitative theory of verisimilitude. Br J Philos Sci 25:166–177

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto I (1987) Truthlikeness. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto I (1998) Verisimilitude: the third period. Br J Philos Sci 49:1–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto I (1999) Belief revision and truth likeness. In: Hansson B, Halldén S, Sahlin N-E, Rabinowicz W (eds) Internet Festschrift for Peter Gärdenfors. URL http://www.lucs.lu.se/ spinning/

  • Oddie G (1986) Likeness to truth. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper KR (1963) Conjectures and refutations: the growth of scientific knowledge. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper KR (1972) Objective knowledge. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Rott H (2000) Two dogmas of belief revision. J Philos 97:503–522

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tichý P (1974) On Popper’s definitions of verisimilitude. Br J Philos Sci 25:155–160

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The authors wish to express their gratitude to Roberto Festa and Theo A. F. Kuipers for commenting on an early draft of the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gustavo Cevolani .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2009 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Cevolani, G., Calandra, F. (2009). Approaching the Truth via Belief Change in Propositional Languages. In: Suárez, M., Dorato, M., Rédei, M. (eds) EPSA Epistemology and Methodology of Science. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-3263-8_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics