Skip to main content
Log in

Brandom, Peirce, and the overlooked friction of contrapiction

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Contra Rorty, we cannot do everything—and more—with the Wittgensteinian notion of language-game that the pragmatists were trying to do with experience.

Vincent Colapietro (2010, p. 20)

Abstract

Robert Brandom holds that what we mean is best understood in terms of what inferences we are prepared to defend, and that such a defence is best understood in terms of rule-governed social interactions. This manages to explain quite a lot. However, for those who think that there is more to making correct/incorrect inferences than obeying/breaking accepted rules, Brandom’s account fails to adequately capture what it means to reason properly. Thus, in an effort to sketch an alternative that does not rely primarily on peer pressure, I draw on the work of C. S. Peirce. Peirce argued that, when we reason, we manipulate abstract diagrams in order to observe what results. Since some manipulations are barred by the self-same nature of the diagrams, I try to show that this qualitative incompatibility, which I dub “contrapiction,” is a good (non-social) reason to regard some reasoning as bad.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Aristotle (1984). In Barnes, J. (Ed.), The complete works of Aristotle (2 Vols). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

  • Brandom, R. B. (1994). Making it explicit: Reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. B. (1995). Knowledge and the social articulation of the space of reasons. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 55(4), 895–908.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. B. (2000). Articulating reasons: An introduction to inferentialism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. B. (2008). Between saying and doing: Toward an analytic pragmatism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. B. (2009). Reason in philosophy: Animating ideas. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. B. (2011). Perspectives on pragmatism: Classical, recent, and contemporary. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. B. (2015). From empiricism to expressivism: Brandom reads sellars. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (2007). Is rationality normative? Disputatio, 2(23), 161–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burch, R. W. (1994). Game-theoretical semantics for Peirce’s existential graphs. Synthese, 99(3), 361–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Champagne, M. (2014a). Just do it: Schopenhauer and Peirce on the immediacy of agency. Symposium: Canadian Journal of Continental Philosophy, 18(2), 209–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Champagne, M. (2014b). Referring to the qualitative dimension of consciousness: Iconicity instead of indexicality. Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review, 53(1), 135–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Champagne, M. (2014c). Semiotics. Oxford Bibliographies in Philosophy. doi:10.1093/OBO/9780195396577-0179.

  • Champagne, M. (2015a). Disjunctivism and the ethics of disbelief. Philosophical Papers, 44(2), 139–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Champagne, M. (2015b). Experience and life as ever-present constraints on knowledge. Metaphilosophy, 46(2), 235–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Champagne, M. (2015c). Poinsot versus Peirce on merging with reality by sharing a quality. Versus, 120, 31–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Champagne, M. (2015d). Sound reasoning (literally): Prospects and challenges of current acoustic logics. Logica Universalis, 9(3), 331–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chevalier, J.-M. (2014). Why ought we to be logical? Peirce’s naturalism on norms and rational requirements. In J. Dutant, D. Fassio, & A. Meylan (Eds.), Liber Amicorum Pascal Engel (pp. 716–740). Geneva: Université de Genève.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. J. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colapietro, V. M. (2010). Peirce today. Pragmatism Today, 1(2), 7–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coltheart, M. (1980). Iconic memory and visible persistence. Perception and Psychophysics, 27(3), 183–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A., & Lepore, E. (1992). Holism: A shopper’s guide. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillies, D. (2009). Problem-solving and the problem of induction. In Z. Parusniková & R. S. Cohen (Eds.), Rethinking Popper (pp. 103–115). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ketner, K. L. (1981). The best example of semiosis and its use in teaching semiotics. The American Journal of Semiotics, 1(1–2), 47–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lance, M. (2000). The word made flesh: Toward a neo-sellarsian view of concepts, analysis, and understanding. Acta Analytica, 15(25), 117–135.

    Google Scholar 

  • Legg, C. (2008). The problem of the essential icon. American Philosophical Quarterly, 45(3), 207–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lumer, C. (1988). The disputation—a special type of cooperative argumentative dialogue. Argumentation, 2(4), 441–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maher, C. (2012). The Pittsburgh school of philosophy: Sellars, McDowell, Brandom. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. H. (2002). Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. H. (2009). The engaged intellect: Philosophical essays. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Misak, C. (2013). The American pragmatists. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, C. W. (1971). Writings on the general theory of signs. The Hague: Mouton.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Norman, A. P. (2001). The normative structure of adjudicative dialogue. Argumentation, 15(4), 489–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paavola, S. (2011). Diagrams, iconicity, and abductive discovery. Semiotica, 186(1–4), 297–314.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1931–1958). The collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce (Vols. 1–6 edited by C. Hartshorne and P. Weiss, Vols. 7–8 edited by A. W. Burks). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Peirce, C. S. (1982). In Fisch, M. H. (Ed.), The writings of Charles S. Peirce: A chronological edition (Vol. 1). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Peirce, C. S. (1992). In Houser, N., et al. (Eds.), The essential Peirce (Vol. 1). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Peirce, C. S. (1998). In Houser, N., et al. (Eds.), The essential Peirce (Vol. 2). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Peirce, C. S. (2015a). In Pietarinen, A.-V. (Ed.), Logic of the future: Peirce’s writings on existential graphs. Bloomington: Indiana University Press (in press).

  • Peirce, C. S. (2015b). Two papers on existential graphs by Charles Peirce. Edited by Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen. Synthese, 192(4), 881–922.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peregrin, J. (2001). Meaning and structure. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietarinen, A.-V. (2006). Signs of logic: Peircean themes on the philosophy of language, games, and communication. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietarinen, A.-V. (2007). Getting closer to iconic logic. In G. D. Crnkovic & A. J. Stuart (Eds.), Computing, philosophy, and cognitive science: The nexus and the liminal (pp. 53–74). Cambridge: Newcastle upon Tyne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietarinen, A.-V. (2011). Existential graphs: What a diagrammatic logic of cognition might look like. History and Philosophy of Logic, 32(3), 265–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2011). An explorer upon untrodden ground: Peirce on abduction. In D. Gabbay, S. Hartmann, & J. Woods (Eds.), Handbook of the history of logic, vol. 10: Inductive logic (pp. 117–151). Oxford: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1987). How serious a fallacy is inconsistency? Argumentation, 1(3), 303–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, D. D. (1973). The existential graphs of Charles S. Peirce. The Hague: Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. M. (1982). Consequences of pragmatism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sebeok, T. A. (1981). The play of musement. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. In H. Feigl & M. Scriven (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. 1, pp. 253–329). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. ([1963] 1991). Science, perception, and reality. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview.

  • Sellars, W. ([1968] 1992). Science and metaphysics: Variations on Kantian themes. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview.

  • Shimojima, A. (1996). On the efficacy of representation. Doctoral dissertation, Indiana University.

  • Shin, S.-J. (2002). The iconic logic of Peirce’s graphs. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sowa, J. F. (2011). Peirce’s tutorial on existential graphs. Semiotica, 186(1–4), 347–394.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stjernfelt, F. (2000). Diagrams as centerpiece in a Peircean epistemology. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 36(3), 357–392.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stjernfelt, F. (2007). Diagrammatology: An investigation on the borderlines of phenomenology, ontology, and semiotics. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stjernfelt, F. (2014a). Diagrams, narratives and ‘reality’. Sign Systems Studies, 42(2–3), 412–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stjernfelt, F. (2014b). Natural propositions: The actuality of Peirce’s doctrine of dicisigns. Boston: Docent Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wanderer, J. (2008). Robert Brandom. Durham, UK: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, H. (2003). Brandom on practical reason. The Philosophical Quarterly, 23(213), 566–572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, J. J. (2013). Inferential man: An interview with Robert Brandom. Symploke, 21(1–2), 373–397.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. ([1921] 1974). Tractatus logico-philosophicus (D. F. Pears & B. F. McGuinness, Trans.). London and New York: Routledge.

  • Wittgenstein, L. ([1953] 2001). Philosophical investigations (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I want to thank Robert Brandom, Henry Jackman, Erkki Kilpinen, Henrik Rydenfelt, Frederik Stjernfelt, James Burton, Francesco Bellucci, anonymous reviewers for this journal, as well as audience members at the Helsinki Metaphysical Club and the 2015 CLMPS symposium on “Tracking the Diagrammatic Turn in Recent Philosophy of Notation.” This work was conducted as part of the research project Diagrammatic Mind: Logical and Cognitive Aspects of Iconicity, funded by the Academy of Finland and the Estonian Research Council. I am especially indebted to that project’s principal investigator, Prof. Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen, for his continued friendship and support.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marc Champagne.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Champagne, M. Brandom, Peirce, and the overlooked friction of contrapiction. Synthese 193, 2561–2576 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0866-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0866-2

Keywords

Navigation