Skip to main content
Log in

The Persistence of Epistemic Objects Through Scientific Change

  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Why do some epistemic objects persist despite undergoing serious changes, while others go extinct in similar situations? Scientists have often been careless in deciding which epistemic objects to retain and which ones to eliminate; historians and philosophers of science have been on the whole much too unreflective in accepting the scientists’ decisions in this regard. Through a re-examination of the history of oxygen and phlogiston, I will illustrate the benefits to be gained from challenging and disturbing the commonly accepted continuities and discontinuities in the lives of epistemic objects. I will also outline two key consequences of such re-thinking. First, a fresh view on the (dis)continuities in key epistemic objects is apt to lead to informative revisions in recognized periods and trends in the history of science. Second, recognizing sources of continuity leads to a sympathetic view on extinct objects, which in turn problematizes the common monistic tendency in science and philosophy; this epistemological reorientation allows room for more pluralism in scientific practice itself.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For further details, see Chang (2009b), Chang (2010), and Chang (2012), chapter 1.

  2. It would have been better to go with Scheele in calling the stuff “fire air”, or to follow Oersted’s example in coining a more sensible term in one’s own language.

  3. Lavoisier does the same for hydrogen and nitrogen, too.

  4. This makes an important contrast to the case of the term “acid” (from Arrhenius onward), which Stanford and Kitcher (2000, pp. 115–120) discuss at some length.

  5. What I mean by “operational” goes back to Percy W. Bridgman’s work, as explicated in Chang (2009a). My own conception of “epistemic activity” is yet to be fully spelled out, but some indication is given in Chang (2008).

  6. For a preliminary attempt, see “Acidity: The Persistence of the Everyday in the Scientific”, presentation at the joint meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association and the History of Science Society, 4 November 2010.

  7. See Chang (2009b) for further reflections on this historiographical point.

  8. Kuhn (1970), 157.

  9. This quirky fact I owe to Partington and McKie (1937–1939, p. 350).

  10. For full details on this episode, see chapter 2 of Chang (2012).

  11. I thank Patrick Coffey for alerting me to this passage.

  12. For details about various aspects of Dalton’s atomism, see Cardwell (1968).

  13. Various historians have traced the rise of the building-block ontology in chemistry; for example, see Siegfried (2002) and Klein (1994, 1996).

  14. For a helpful definition of monism, see Kellert et al. (2006, p. x).

  15. For the full argument, see Chang (2012), chapter 5.

References

  • Allchin, D. (1992). Phlogiston after oxygen. Ambix, 39, 110–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arabatzis, T. (2006). Representing electrons: A biographical approach to theoretical entities. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bensaude-Vincent, B. (1996). Between history and memory: Centennial and bicentennial images of Lavoisier. Isis, 87, 481–499.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cardwell, D. S. L. (Ed.). (1968). John Dalton and the progress of science. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2004). Inventing temperature: Measurement and scientific progress. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2008). Contingent transcendental arguments for metaphysical principles. In M. Massimi (Ed.), Kant and philosophy of science today (pp. 113–133). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2009a). “Operationalism”, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Online at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/operationalism.

  • Chang, H. (2009b). We have never been whiggish (about phlogiston). Centaurus, 51, 239–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2010). The hidden history of phlogiston: How philosophical failure can generate historiographical refinement. HYLEInternational Journal for Philosophy of Chemistry, 16, 47–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2012). Is water H 2 O? Evidence, pluralism and realism. Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Conant, J. B. (1957). The overthrow of the phlogiston theory: The Chemical Revolution of 1775–1789. In J. B. Conant (Ed.), Harvard case histories in experimental science (Vol. 1, pp. 65–115). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daston, L. (Ed.). (2000). Biographies of scientific objects. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, J. (1780). Philosophical observations on the senses of vision and hearing; to which are added, a treatise on harmonic sounds, and an essay on combustion and animal heat. London: J. Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2008). Thomas Kuhn and the Chemical Revolution. Foundations of Chemistry, 10, 101–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kellert, S. H., Longino, H. E., & Waters, C. K. (Eds.). (2006). Scientific pluralism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, U. (1994). Origin of the concept of chemical compound. Science in Context, 7(2), 163–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, U. (1996). The chemical workshop tradition and the experimental practice: Discontinuities within continuities. Science in Context, 9(3), 251–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, U., & Lefèvre, W. (2007). Materials in eighteenth-century science. Cambridge, Mass: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd ed.). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lavoisier, A.-L. (1789). Traité élémentaire de chimie. Paris: Cuchet.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lavoisier, A.-L. (1965). Elements of chemistry, with an introduction by D. McKie. New York: Dover (reprint of R. Kerr’s English translation (1790) of Lavoisier 1789).

  • Lewis, G. N. (1926). The anatomy of science. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McEvoy, J. G. (1997). Positivism, whiggism, and the Chemical Revolution: A study in the historiography of chemistry. History of Science, 35, 1–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odling, W. (1871). On the revived theory of phlogiston (address at the Royal Institution, 28 April 1871). Proceedings of the Royal Institution of Great Britain, 6, 315–325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partington, J. R., & McKie, D. (1937–1939). Historical studies on the phlogiston theory. Annals of Science, 2, 361–404; 3, 1–58, 337–371; 4, 113–149 (in four parts).

  • Rheinberger, H.-J. (1997). Toward a history of epistemic things: Synthesizing proteins in the test tube. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger, H.-J. (2005). A reply to David Bloor: ‘Toward a sociology of epistemic things’. Perspectives on Science, 13, 406–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Siegfried, R. (2002). From elements to atoms: A history of chemical composition. Philadelphia: American Philosophical Society.

  • Stanford, P. K., & Kitcher, P. (2000). Refining the causal theory of reference for natural kind terms. Philosophical Studies, 97, 99–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sudduth, W. M. (1978). Eighteenth-century identifications of electricity with phlogiston. Ambix, 25, 131–147.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Uljana Feest and Thomas Sturm for inviting me to the workshop on historical epistemology at the Max Planck Institute where this paper was originally presented, and also for their effective guidance through the publication process. I also thank many other participants and hosts of the workshop for their helpful comments and kind encouragement, especially Philip Kitcher, Paul Hoyningen-Huene, Hans-Jörg Rheinberger, and Lorraine Daston.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hasok Chang.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Chang, H. The Persistence of Epistemic Objects Through Scientific Change. Erkenn 75, 413–429 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-011-9340-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-011-9340-9

Keywords

Navigation