Skip to main content
Log in

Ideological parsimony

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The theoretical virtue of parsimony values the minimizing of theoretical commitments, but theoretical commitments come in two kinds: ontological and ideological. While the ontological commitments of a theory are the entities it posits, a theory’s ideological commitments are the primitive concepts it employs. Here, I show how we can extend the distinction between quantitative and qualitative parsimony, commonly drawn regarding ontological commitments, to the domain of ideological commitments. I then argue that qualitative ideological parsimony is a theoretical virtue. My defense proceeds by demonstrating the merits of qualitative ideological parsimony and by showing how the qualitative conception of ideological parsimony undermines two notable arguments from ideological parsimony: David Lewis’ defense of modal realism and Ted Sider’s defense of mereological nihilism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. On theoretical virtues in general, see Kuhn (1977). On fertility, see Nolan (1999). On conservativeness, see (Lewis 1986, p. 235). On theoretical virtues as sources of epistemic reasons, see (Harman 1997).

  2. On the connection between theoretical virtues and rationality, see McMullin (1976). See also Psillos (1999) on the role of parsimony in abductive arguments for scientific realism.

  3. On the abductive response to skepticism, see Vogel (1990).

  4. It is not obvious that the existence of a divine being would support (Parsimony). One might, for example, draw a contrary, broadly Leibnizian conclusion that reality is maximally rather than minimally populated.

  5. For an overview of efforts to defend (Parsimony), see Foley (1993), Sober (1975), and Smart (1984).

  6. (Parsons (1976), p. 660).

  7. See Quine (1953a).

  8. See Quine (1953a). On the implementation of the Quinean approach to ontology, see Colyvan (2001).

  9. On Quinean meta-ontology and ontological commitment, see Van Inwagen (1998).

  10. My thanks here to an anonymous referee for noting this concern about scientific commitments.

  11. I omit complications about the restrictions of a Quinean regimentation in first-order logic. As will be clear, some of theories of interest here invoke modal operators and are therefore anathema to the Quinean, but the core Quinean notion of ontological commitment is all that will be required for what follows.

  12. (Quine (1951), p. 14).

  13. Not all accounts of the representational power of theories admit something like the distinction between ideology and ontology. For example, algorithmic information-theoretic approaches to model selection suggest at least one understanding of “representational power” where representational power, given a compressible body of data and fixed language, is determined by the minimal description length that outputs the data in question. On algorithmic complexity, see Li and Vitanyi (1997). Notably, this construal of representational power provides a prima facie rationale for parsimony within the context of model selection. Here, I assume the Quinean conception of theories and the corresponding understanding of representational power.

  14. As (Quine (1951), p. 14) puts it, “As a subdivision of ideology there is the question of what ideas are fundamental or primitive for a theory, and what ones derivative.”

  15. Quine (1953b) defends eliminativism. On modalism, see Melia (1992). Note that a defender of possible worlds is not a modalist in the relevant sense. The modalist eschews quantification over possible worlds of any kind, using only primitive modal operators to express modal claims. For present purposes, I set aside concerns about the ontological status of facts.

  16. Is there an analogue of fundamental rather than derivative ideological commitments in terms of ontological commitments? Perhaps. Some philosophers have argued that ontological commitments only contribute to the cost of a theory if they are fundamental rather than merely derivative ontological commitments. See Schaffer (2010) for discussion. Here, I assume a “flat” Quinean conception of ontology: no objects are more or less fundamental than other objects even while objects instantiate more or less fundamental properties.

  17. Here, the ‘O’ in O-Parsimony and ‘I’ in I-Parsimony stand for ‘ontological’ and ‘ideological’, respectively.

  18. See (Sider (2011), p. 14) for discussion of ideological parsimony. See also Melia (2008) for a discussion of parsimony and its implications for nominalism.

  19. See Cortens and O’Leary-Hawthorne (1995) for discussion.

  20. See Quine (1976), Turner (2011), and Dasgupta (2010) on the implications of “functorese” for ontology.

  21. See Sider (2006) for discussion of the ideological and ontological solutions to the puzzle of how bare particulars are unified with their properties.

  22. See Lewis (1983) for discussion of the analytic options regarding the concept of natural properties.

  23. This does not require that there is some fixed value we can assign to commitments—it would, after all, be surprising to learn that, any primitive concept is equal in value to any collection of thirteen objects—but, rather, that both ontology and ideology figure equally into the evaluation of theories.

  24. On algorithmic information theory and Kolmogorov complexity, see Li and Vitanyi (1997) and Grunwald and Paul (2008). On the role of algorithmic information theory and minimum description length theory in model selection, see McAllister (2007).

  25. (Benacerraf et al. (1966), p. 35) express the opposing skeptical view rather succinctly: “It is hard enough to believe that the natural world is so nicely arranged that what is simplest, etc., by our lights is always the same as what is true (or, at least, generally the same as what is true); why should one believe that the universe of sets... is so nicely arranged that there is a pre-established harmony between our feelings of simplicity, etc., and truth?” (Italics from original.)

  26. Here, ‘N’ in NO-Parsimony and ‘K’ in KO-Parsimony stand for ‘quantitative and ‘qualitative’, respectively. Since ‘Q’ won’t do the trick, I’ve opted for ‘N’ and ‘K’ with ‘number’ and ‘kind’ in mind.

  27. Nolan (1997) presents some evidence of the reasonable employment of (NO-Parsimony) within physical theory. See Baker (2003) for an examination of those cases where quantitative parsimony is a source of justification on the grounds of improved explanatory power.

  28. I assume here that neither murderer nor set is a natural kind. While controversial, I take it that a necessary condition for kindhood is figuring into the qualitative features of the world that are tracked by the natural sciences.

  29. Here, I omit a range of complications for the proposed analyses of both intrinsicality and duplication. While important, my primary aim here is illustrative in nature. I therefore assume that these proposals are unproblematic. On an alternative strategy for analyzing intrinsicality, see Trogdon (2009).

  30. As Lewis (1983) and others have suggested, a primitive concept of naturalness might serve as an additional primitive that allows for the analysis of duplication and therefore intrinsicality. Again, for the sake of illustration, I set aside this complication.

  31. Sider (2011) cites the question of whether our mereological theory ought to take overlap or parthood as primitive. I take the present considerations to apply equally well to that case.

  32. As (Sider (2011), p.13) says, “Should our fundamental logical theory take conjunction and negation, or instead, disjunction and negation as primitive? In such cases it’s hard to see how to choose, and indeed, hard to believe there could be a single correct choice.” See also Sider’s discussion of the universal and existential quantifiers.

  33. See (Sider (2011), p.13).

  34. Unsurprisingly, some will believe this example to be genuinely substantial, if so, I encourage them to consider whether any of the debates they hold to be insubstantial can be resolved in the manner I suggest.

  35. This ranking should capture not only an ordering of properties, but also the metric structure of these properties (e.g., how far apart certain more or less natural properties are from one another). Here, I set aside the requirement of supplying a metric structure to naturalness and focus on the categorical and comparative naturalness primitives only. See Eddon (forthcoming) for discussion.

  36. See Sider (forthcoming) for discussion.

  37. See Sider (2011) for discussion of absolutist and comparativist views of structure.

  38. The proper formulation of presentism and eternalism is a matter of some disagreement. See, for example, Crisp (2004) and Caplan and Sanson (2010).

  39. I omit discussion of the “moving gap” view, according to which only past and future entities exist, and the present is distinguished from other times by virtue of its nonexistence. I am sincerely hopeful no one will be troubled by this omission.

  40. On the methodological assumptions crucial to this argument, see Cameron (2007a) and Daly (2008).

  41. See Bricker (2006) for a defense of modal realism without appeal to theoretical virtues as a source of epistemic reasons.

  42. Here, I take the relevant concept of modality to include at least the operators of modal logic, but I leave open what precisely this concept of modality subsumes.

  43. Fine cites a range of other properties that the modal view errantly deems essential to Socrates: being distinct from the Eiffel Tower, being such that \(1+2=3\), and being such that Plato is essentially human.

  44. Sider (2011) remarks that “Fine convincingly argues against the standard modal definition of essence.” See Correia (2006) for a similar assessment.

  45. In defense of island universes, see Bricker (1996).

  46. Lewis (1986) holds that the isolation and unification of worlds is determined by either spatiotemporal or what he calls “analogically spatiotemporal relations.” See Bricker (1996) for a defense of an extended conception of isolation and unification that appeals to external relations (i.e., relations that fail to supervene upon the intrinsic natures of their relata).

  47. On absolute actuality, see Bricker (2006).

  48. (KI-Parsimony) also has consequences for another modal metaphysical thesis: modalism, according to which there are no possible worlds and modal operators are irreducible primitives required to express modal facts. A powerful objection to modalism holds that the theory is untenable because, in order to match the expressive power of views that quantify over possible worlds, the modalist requires a plurality of distinct, individually indexed actuality operators. For ersatzist actualists, this commitment is taken to either undermine the theory or show it to be a mere notational variant of views that accept abstract possible worlds. But, if (KI-Parsimony) is true, there is good reason to believe that all these actuality operators are of a common kind, so modalism is on equal footing with (and perhaps superior to) standard forms of ersatz actualism, which help themselves to primitive modality as well as abstract entities that play the role of possible worlds.

  49. Strictly speaking, the view Sider defends cannot be stated using mereological vocabulary since Sider rejects commitment to the ideology of mereology. Here, I omit these particular complications. On nihilism, see Dorr and Rosen (2001) and Liggins (2008). Here, I focus my attention on those forms of nihilism, which identify mereological atoms with microphysical objects. See Schaffer (2007) for discussion of monistic mereological nihilism.

  50. Competitors to nihilism include universalism, according to which any objects compose a further object, as well as organicism, according to which only organic objects have proper parts, and brutalism, according to which there is no reductive account of the conditions under which composition occurs. See Rea (1998) for a defense of universalism. See Van Inwagen (1990) for a defense of organicism. See Markosian (1998) for a defense of brutalism.

  51. Sider (forthcoming).

  52. For a dissenting opinion, see Cameron (2007b).

  53. On the topic-neutral nature of mereology, see (Lewis (1991), pp. 72–87).

  54. Defenders of the Principle of the Identity of Indiscernibles might lay claim to an analysis of identity, but, while individual identity may admit of analysis in terms of shared properties, this merely pushes the bump in the rug, since an analysis of property identity is still required.

  55. For discussion of various interpretations of “composition as identity,” see Cotnoir (forthcoming).

References

  • Baker, D. (2003). Quantitative parsimony and explanatory power. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 54, 245–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf, P., & Putnam, H. (1966). Introduction. In Philosophy of mathematics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Bricker, P. (1996). Isolation and unification: The realist analysis of possible worlds. Philosophical Studies, 84, 225–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bricker, P. (2006). Absolute actuality and the plurality of worlds. Philosophical Perspectives, 20, 41–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, R. (2007a). Lewisian realism: Methodology, epistemology, and circularity. Synthese, 156, 143–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, R. (2007b). The contingency of composition. Philosophical Studies, 136, 99–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caplan, B., & Sanson, D. (2010). The way things were. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81, 24–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M. (2001). The indispensability of mathematics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Correia, F. (2006). Generic essence, objectual essence, and modality. Nous, 40, 753–767.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cortens, A., & O’Leary-Hawthorne, J. (1995). Towards ontological nihilism. Philosophical Studies, 79, 143–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cotnoir, A. (forthcoming). Composition as general identity. In Oxford studies in metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Crisp, T. M. (2004). Presentism and triviality. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, 1, 15–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daly, C. J. (2008). The methodology of genuine modal realism. Synthese, 162, 37–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, S. (2010). Individuals: An essay in revisionary metaphysics. Philosophical Studies, 145, 35–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dorr, C., & Rosen, G. (2001). Composition as fiction. In G. Richard (Ed.), Blackwell handbook of metaphysics. Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Eddon, M. (forthcoming). Fundamental properties of fundamental properties. In Oxford studies in metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Fine, K. (1994). Essence and modality. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foley, R. (1993). What’s to be said for simplicity? Philosophical Issues, 3, 209–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grunwald P., & Paul V. (2008). Algorithmic information theory. In P. Adriaans et al. (Eds.), Philosophy of information. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

  • Harman, G. (1997). Pragmatism and reasons for belief. In C. B. Kulp (Ed.), Realism/anti-realism and epistemology. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.

  • Kuhn, T. (1977). Objectivity, value judgement and theory choice. In The essential tension. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61, 343–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1991). Parts of classes. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Li, M., & Vitanyi, P. (1997). An introduction to Kolmogorov complexity and its applications. New York: Springer.

  • Liggins, D. (2008). Nihilism without self-contradition. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 62, 177–196.

    Google Scholar 

  • Markosian, N. (1998). Brutal composition. Philosophical Studies, 92, 211–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McAllister, J. (2007). Model selection and the multiplicity of patterns in empirical data. Philosophy of Science, 74, 884–894.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, E. (1976). Fertility and the unit of appraisal in science. In R.S. Cohen et al (Eds.), Essays in Memory of Imre Lakatos. Dordrecth: Reidel

  • Melia, J. (1992). Against modalism. Philosophical Studies, 68, 35–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melia, J. (2008). A world of concrete particulars. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, 4, 99–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nolan, D. (1997). Quantitative parsimony. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 48, 329–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nolan, D. (1999). Is fertility virtuous in iIts own right? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 50, 265–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, T. (1976). The methodology of nonexistence. Journal of Philosophy, 76, 649–662.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism. London: Routledge Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1951). Ontology and ideology. Philosophical Studies, 1, 11–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1953a). On what there is. In From a logical point of view. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1953b). Reference and modality. In From a logical point of view. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1976). Algebraic logic and predicate functors. In Ways of paradox. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Rea, M. (1998). In defense of mereological universalism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58, 347–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2007). From nihilism to monism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 85, 175–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2010). The least discerning and most promiscuous truthmaker. Philosophical Quarterly, 60, 307–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smart J. J. C. (1984). Ockham’s Razor. In J. H. Fetzer (Ed.), Principles of philosophical reasoning. Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Allanheld.

  • Sober, E. (1975). Simplicity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2006). Bare particulars. Philosophical Perspectives, 20, 387–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2011). Writing the book of the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (forthcoming). Against parthood. In Oxford studies in metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Trogdon, K. (2009). Monism and intrinsicality. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 87, 127–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turner, J. (2011). Ontological nihilism. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, 6, 3–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (1990). Material beings. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (1998). Meta-ontology. Erkenntnis, 48, 233–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vogel, J. (1990). Cartesian skepticism and inference to the best explanation. Journal of Philosophy, 87, 658–666.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

For helpful comments and discussion, thanks to Marc Alspector-Kelly, Phil Bricker, Ben Caplan, Ed Ferrier, Barak Krakauer, Chris Meacham, and Alex Skiles.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sam Cowling.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Cowling, S. Ideological parsimony. Synthese 190, 3889–3908 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-012-0231-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-012-0231-7

Keywords

Navigation