Skip to main content
Log in

Palliative sedation, foregoing life-sustaining treatment, and aid-in-dying: what is the difference?

  • Published:
Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

After a review of terminology, I identify—in addition to Margaret Battin’s list of five primary arguments for and against aid-in-dying—the argument from functional equivalence as another primary argument. I introduce a novel way to approach this argument based on Bernard Lonergan’s generalized empirical method (GEM). Then I proceed on the basis of GEM to distinguish palliative sedation, palliative sedation to unconsciousness when prognosis is less than two weeks, and foregoing life-sustaining treatment from aid-in-dying. I conclude (1) that aid-in-dying must be justified on its own merits and not on the basis of these well-established palliative care practices; and (2) that societies must decide, in weighing the merits of aid-in-dying, whether or not to make the judgment that no life is better than life-like-this (however this is specified) part of their operative value structure.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. At present, the following professional organizations do not support legalization of aid-in-dying: National Hospice and Palliative Care Organization [4], Hospice and Palliative Nurses Association [5], American Nurses Association [6], American Medical Association [7].

  2. Both cases—VSED and refusal of ANH—call for good palliative supportive care [11]. This includes assessing whether the patient’s decision is complicated by depression or some other potentially correctable factor. If this is the case, attending to the decisional process may resolve the issue of eating and drinking in VSED, but not in refusal of ANH without also attending to the details of resuming ANH.

  3. However, see Morita el al. [23] and Claessens et al. [24] for studies of palliative sedation that specify such measures.

  4. Corresponding to -4 (no response to voice, but any movement in response to physical stimulation) or -5 (no response to voice or physical stimulation) on the Richmond Agitation-Sedation Scale [27].

  5. Besides Rachels [29], among many others who rely on the argument from functional equivalence, see Brock [30, 31] and Kamm [32].

  6. Data of sense include colors, odors, sounds, and so forth; data of consciousness include acts of seeing, smelling, hearing, perceiving, inquiring, understanding, reflecting, judging, and so forth [33, p. 299].

  7. “The anticipation of a constant system to be discovered grounds classical method; the anticipation of an intelligibly related sequence of systems grounds genetic method; the anticipation that data will not conform to system grounds statistical method; and the anticipation that the relations between the successive stages of changing system will not be directly intelligible grounds dialectical method. But data must either conform or not conform to system, and successive systems must be either related or not related in a directly intelligible manner. Accordingly, taken together, the four methods are relevant to any field of data; they do not dictate what data must be; they are able to cope with data no matter what they may prove to be” [33, pp. 509–510].

  8. Like the x in algebra, heuristic definition anticipates an answer to a question or a problem; value is what one expects to determine in making choices about what to do.

  9. For Lonergan, our acts of experiencing feelings in a particular situation, understanding the situation and its ramifications, sorting out what is really going on and what is best to do, and deciding to act accordingly—all of this—is integrated both on the side of the situation under consideration (the object) and on the side of the person performing these acts (the subject) [33, pp. 349–352]. Intentionality refers to the object-relatedness of all conscious acts; it includes but extends beyond the meaning of intention as the object of feeling (motive) and as the object of choice (goal or value).

  10. It often helps loved ones to sort out their intentions in making end-of-life decisions with potentially bad effects for the patient to ask: would I be satisfied with the outcome of this decision if the bad effect does not occur?

  11. According to this study, the median Glasgow Coma Score dropped from 12 or better a week before death to 9 on day of death (with 8 being the cutoff for coma).

  12. This should not mean short-circuiting the spiritual, social, and emotional dimensions of hospice care, neither for the patient prior to deep sedation nor for the patient’s loved ones throughout the dying and grieving process [20]; but see [49] regarding these very factors contributing to nurses’ distress around the practice of palliative sedation.

  13. In this case, nurses usually administer the medication(s) which hasten death, albeit with physician’s orders. With PAD, a patient self-administers the medication in question; with VE, a physician administers it [12].

  14. These same two questions play a prominent role in H. Richard Niebuhr’s account of an ethics of responsibility in The Responsible Self [53]. To my knowledge, Lonergan and Niebuhr worked independently of one another, although both developed their ideas within a context of concern for authenticity following the Second World War.

  15. Calling both practices by the same name, palliative sedation to unconsciousness, obscures this difference. They should be named differently; for instance, rapid deep sedation of the imminently dying and continuous deep sedation for existential suffering.

  16. Coordinating VSED with PSU amounts to aid-in-dying, both factually and intentionally. However, when a patient chooses VSED independent of a decision to employ PSU, then a physician need not be complicit in hastening death by continuing to attend to the patient’s psychosocial-spiritual needs, as well as to symptoms such as pain or dyspnea. This situation may involve a significant difference in perspective for patient and physician regarding the particular circumstances and ultimate value of the patient’s life. I deal with this further in the next section of this paper.

  17. The claim that PSU is equivalent to aid-in-dying because permanent loss of consciousness amounts to brain death requires a separate analysis [56], which I defer since the end-of-life situations in which contested definitions of brain death are pivotal do not involve patients who are aware of distressing symptoms—as is the case with PSU.

  18. He states candidly and omnisciently that both Smith and Jones enter a bathroom with the same intent to kill a young boy and that both continue to act on this basis despite different circumstances until each boy is dead. This singular intent is the very basis on which each man is considered responsible for the death of the boy in question.

  19. The same considerations apply to the patient with a potentially favorable prognosis who voluntarily stops eating and drinking, although in this case, as indicated earlier, eating and drinking do not constitute a treatment.

  20. Duffy [66] describes a change in attitude toward aid-in-dying as it has affected his practice in ways that would be hard to quantify on a slippery slope metric.

  21. In comparison to Daniel Sulmasy [68], as I mentioned above, Lonergan identifies goods of order intermediate between the empirical and transcendental orders of value. Fred Lawrence puts Lonergan’s tripartite structure of value and the human good in historical perspective: “Aristotle defined the good as the object of appetite…. Thomas [Aquinas] made explicit a more intellectual dimension of the good as good of order…. [Lonergan] goes beyond this to specify more clearly the notion of the good as what is intended in questions for deliberation” [69, p. 141]. We are originators of value in being able to ask and answer questions concerning the worth of what we do. In this sense, we condition the possibility of value judgments and are ourselves of transcendental value.

  22. Henk ten Have and Jos Welie [65, p. 175] come to this conclusion in their analysis of the practice of aid-in-dying in the Netherlands: “The practice of euthanasia … is justified by physicians and in terms of medical criteria.… The Dutch euthanasia movement started as a protest against medical power, emphasizing patient autonomy as a counterbalance. But after 30 years of debate, the power of medicine appears only to have increased because physicians decide whether patients’ suffering is so unbearable that euthanasia is indicated”.

  23. On February 6, 2015, the Supreme Court of Canada published its decision to remove Canada’s prohibition on physician-assisted dying to worldwide notice. The justices were explicit about arguing from self-determination, but deemed it unnecessary to unpack the disvalued quality of life judgment implicit in their decision relative to equal treatment for persons with disabilities [70].

References

  1. Orentlicher, D., T.M. Pope, and B.A. Rich. 2014. The changing legal climate for physician aid in dying. Journal of the American Medical Association 311: 1961–1962.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Campbell, C.S., and M.A. Black. 2014. Dignity, death, and dilemmas: A study of Washington hospices and physician-assisted death. Journal of Pain and Symptom Management 47: 137–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Siegel, A.M., D.A. Sisti, and A.L. Caplan. 2014. Pediatric euthanasia in Belgium: Disturbing developments. Journal of the American Medical Association 311: 1963–1964.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. National Hospice and Palliative Care Organization. 2005. Commentary and resolution on physician assisted suicide. National Hospice & Palliative Care Organization archive. http://www.nhpco.org/sites/default/files/public/PAS_Resolution_Commentary.pdf. Accessed on August 26, 2014.

  5. Hospice and Palliative Nurses Association. 2011. Legalization of assisted suicide. Hospice and Palliative Nurses Association archive. https://www.hpna.org/DisplayPage.aspx?Title1=Position%20Statements. Accessed on August 26, 2014.

  6. American Nurses Association. 2013. Euthanasia, assisted suicide, and aid in dying. American Nurses Association archive. http://www.nursingworld.org/positionstatements. Accessed on August 26, 2014.

  7. American Medical Association. 2013. AMA’s code of ethics. American Medical Association archive. http://www.ama-assn.org/ama/pub/physician-resources/medical-ethics/code-medical-ethics.page? Accessed on August 26, 2014.

  8. Battin, M.P. 2005. Ending life: Ethics and the way we die. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  9. Lynn, J., J. Harrold, and J.L. Schuster. 2011. Handbook for mortals, 2nd ed. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Pope, T.M., and A. West. 2014. Legal briefing: Voluntarily stopping eating and drinking. Journal of Clinical Ethics 25(1): 68–80.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Eddy, D.M. 1994. A piece of my mind: A conversation with my mother. Journal of the American Medical Association 272: 179–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Quill, T.E., B. Lo, and D.W. Brock. 1997. Palliative options of last resort: A comparison of voluntarily stopping eating and drinking, terminal sedation, physician-assisted suicide, and voluntary active euthanasia. Journal of the American Medical Association 278: 2099–2104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Broeckaert, B. 2000. Palliative sedation defined or why and when sedation is not euthanasia. Journal of Pain and Symptom Management 20: S58.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Jansen, L.A., and D.P. Sulmasy. 2002. Sedation, alimentation, hydration, and equivocation: Careful conversation about care at the end of life. Annals of Internal Medicine 136(11): 845–849.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Morita, T., Y. Chinone, M. Ikenaga, et al. 2005. Ethical validity of palliative sedation therapy: A multicenter, prospective, observational study conducted on specialized palliative care units in Japan. Journal of Pain and Symptom Management 30: 308–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Dean, M.M., V. Cellarius, B. Henry, D. Oneschuk, and S.L. Librach. 2012. Framework for continuous palliative sedation therapy in Canada. Journal of Palliative Medicine 15: 870–879.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Quill, T.E., B. Lo, D.W. Brock, and A. Meisel. 2009. Last-resort options for palliative sedation. Annals of Internal Medicine 151(6): 421–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Raus, K., J. Brown, C. Seale, et al. 2014. Continuous sedation until death: The everyday moral reasoning of physicians, nurses and family caregivers in the UK, The Netherlands and Belgium. BMC Medical Ethics 15: 14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Rys, S., F. Mortier, L. Deliens, R. Deschepper, M.P. Battin, and J. Bilsen. 2013. Continuous sedation until death: Moral justifications of physicians and nurses—A content analysis of opinion pieces. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 16: 533–542.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. ten Have, H., and J.V. Welie. 2014. Palliative sedation versus euthanasia: An ethical assessment. Journal of Pain and Symptom Management 47: 123–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Davis, M.P., and P.A. Ford. 2005. Palliative sedation definition, practice, outcomes, and ethics. Journal of Palliative Medicine 8: 699–701; author reply 702-3.

  22. Brinkkemper, T., A.M. van Norel, K.M. Szadek, S.A. Loer, W.W. Zuurmond, and R.S. Perez. 2013. The use of observational scales to monitor symptom control and depth of sedation in patients requiring palliative sedation: A systematic review. Palliative Medicine 27: 54–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Morita, T., Y. Chinone, M. Ikenaga, et al. 2005. Efficacy and safety of palliative sedation therapy: A multicenter, prospective, observational study conducted on specialized palliative care units in Japan. Journal of Pain and Symptom Management 30: 320–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Claessens, P., J. Menten, P. Schotsmans, and B. Broeckaert. 2012. Level of consciousness in dying patients. The role of palliative sedation: A longitudinal prospective study. American Journal of Hospice & Palliative Care 29: 195–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Billings, J.A. 2014. Palliative sedation. In Palliative care and ethics, ed. T.E. Quill and F.G. Miller, 209–232. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  26. AAHPM Board of Directors. 2006. Statement on palliative sedation. American Association of Hospice and Palliative Medicine archive. http://aahpm.org/positions/palliative-sedation. Accessed on August 26, 2014.

  27. Sessler, C.N., M.S. Gosnell, M.J. Grap, et al. 2002. The Richmond agitation-sedation scale: Validity and reliability in adult intensive care unit patients. American Journal of Respiratory and Critical Care Medicine 166: 1338–1344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Battin, M.P. 2010. The irony of supporting physician-assisted suicide: A personal account. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 13: 403–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Rachels, J. 1975. Active and passive euthanasia. New England Journal of Medicine 292: 78–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Brock, D.W. 1992. Voluntary active euthanasia. Hastings Center Report 22(2): 10–22.

  31. Brock, D.W. 1999. A critique of three objections to physician-assisted suicide. Ethics 109: 519–547.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Kamm, F.M. 2013. Four-step arguments for physician-assisted suicide and euthanasia. In Bioethical prescriptions, 53–83. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  33. Lonergan, B. 1992. Insight. Ed. R.M. Doran and F.E. Crowe. Toronto: Toronto University Press.

  34. Lonergan, B. 1985. A third collection. New York: Paulist Press.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Lonergan, B. 2003. Method in theology. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Lonergan, B. 1988. Cognitional structure. In Collection, ed. F.E. Crowe and R.M. Doran, 205–221. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

  37. Lonergan, B. 2001. Two diagrams. In Phenomenology and logic: The Boston College lectures on mathematical logic and existentialism, ed. P.J. McShane, 319–323. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Aquinas, T. 2012. Summa theologiae. Trans. L. Shapcote. Ed. J. Mortensen and E. Alarcon. Lander, Wyoming: The Aquinas Institute for the Study of Sacred Doctrine.

  39. Quill, T.E. 1993. The ambiguity of clinical intentions. New England Journal of Medicine 329: 1039–1040.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Douglas, C., I. Kerridge, and R. Ankeny. 2008. Managing intentions: The end-of-life administration of analgesics and sedatives, and the possibility of slow euthanasia. Bioethics 22: 388–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. Jansen, L.A. 2010. Disambiguating clinical intentions: The ethics of palliative sedation. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 35: 19–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. Zagar, J. 1984. Acting on principles: A Thomistic perspective in making moral decisions. Lanham, MD: University Press of America Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Aristotle. 2009. Nicomachean ethics. Trans. W.D. Ross. Ed. L. Brown. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  44. Uniacke, S. 2007. The doctrine of double effect. In Principles of health care ethics, 2nd ed, ed. R.E. Ashcroft, 263–268. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Cavanaugh, T.A. 2006. Double-effect reasoning. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  46. McIntyre, A. 2001. Doing away with double effect. Ethics 111: 219–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. Morita, T., J. Tsunoda, S. Inoue, and S. Chihara. 2001. Effects of high dose opioids and sedatives on survival in terminally ill cancer patients. Journal of Pain and Symptom Management 21: 282–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  48. Rousseau, P. 2002. Careful conversation about care at the end of life. Annals of Internal Medicine 137: 1008–1010.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. Morita, T., M. Miyashita, R. Kimura, I. Adachi, and Y. Shima. 2004. Emotional burden of nurses in palliative sedation therapy. Palliative Medicine 18: 550–557.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. Sulmasy, D.P., F. Curlin, G.S. Brungardt, and T. Cavanaugh. 2010. Justifying different levels of palliative sedation. Annals of Internal Medicine 152: 332–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Jansen, L.A. 2003. The moral irrelevance of proximity to death. Journal of Clinical Ethics 14: 49–58.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Berger, J.T. 2010. Rethinking guidelines for the use of palliative sedation. Hastings Center Report 40: 32–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  53. Niebuhr, H.R. 1963. The responsible self. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Lonergan, B. 2004. What are judgments of value? In Philosophical and theological papers 1965–1980, ed. R.M. Doran and F.E. Crowe, 140–156. Toronto: Toronto University Press.

  55. Morita, T., J. Tsunoda, S. Inoue, and S. Chihara. 1999. Survival prediction of terminally ill cancer patients by clinical symptoms: Development of a simple indicator. Japanese Journal of Clinical Oncology 29: 156–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  56. Lipuma, S.H. 2013. Continuous sedation until death as physician-assisted suicide/euthanasia: A conceptual analysis. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 38: 190–204.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Sulmasy, D.P. 1998. Killing and allowing to die: Another look. Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 26: 55–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  58. Rachels, J. 2001. Killing and letting die. In Encyclopedia of ethics, vol. 2, ed. L. Becker and C. Becker, 947–950. New York: Routledge.

  59. Prince-Paul, M., and B.J. Daly. 2005. Ethical considerations in palliative care. In Oxford textbook of palliative nursing, ed. B.R. Ferrell and N. Coyle, 1157–1172. New York: Oxford University Press.

  60. Brock, D.W. 1993. Quality of life measures in health care and medical ethics. In Quality of life, ed. M. Nussbaum and A. Sen, 95–132. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  61. Miller, F.G., J.J. Fins, and L. Snyder. 2000. Assisted suicide compared with refusal of treatment: A valid distinction? University of Pennsylvania Center for Bioethics Assisted Suicide Consensus Panel. Annals of Internal Medicine 132: 470–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  62. Miller, F.G., R.D. Truog, and D.W. Brock. 2010. Moral fictions and medical ethics. Bioethics 24: 453–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  63. Cherny, N.I. 2006. Palliative sedation. In Textbook of palliative medicine, ed. E. Bruera, I.J. Higginson, C. Ripamonti, and C.F. von Gunten, 976–987. London: Hodder Arnold.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Berger, P.T., and T. Luckmann. 1966. The social construction of reality. New York: Irvington Publishers Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  65. ten Have, H.A.M.J., and J.V.M. Welie. 2005. Death and medical power: An ethical analysis of Dutch euthanasia practice. London: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Duffy, T.P. 2014. Physician assistance in dying: A subtler slippery slope. Hastings Center Report 44: 1p following 48.

  67. Welie, J.V., and H.A. ten Have. 2014. The ethics of forgoing life-sustaining treatment: Theoretical considerations and clinical decision making. Multidisciplinary Respiratory Medicine 9: 14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  68. Sulmasy, D.P. 2011. Speaking of the value of life. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 21: 181–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  69. Lawrence, F. 2007. The ethics of authenticity and the human good, in honour of Michael Vertin, an authentic colleague. In The importance of insight: Essays in honour of Michael Vertin, ed. J.J. Liptay, Jr. and D.S. Liptay, 127–150. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

  70. Carter v. Canada (Attorney General), 2015 SCC 5.

Download references

Acknowledgments

Earlier versions of this paper were presented at the West Coast Methods Institute in Los Angeles in April 2014 and at the Lonergan Workshop in Boston in June 2014. I would like to thank David Ndegwah for challenging me to recognize that different viewpoints set the conditions for better understanding, especially during times of rapid historical change.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Patrick Daly.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Daly, P. Palliative sedation, foregoing life-sustaining treatment, and aid-in-dying: what is the difference?. Theor Med Bioeth 36, 197–213 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-015-9329-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-015-9329-5

Keywords

Navigation