Skip to main content
Log in

Objectivity in historical perspective

Lorraine Daston and Peter Galison: Objectivity. New York: Zone Books, 2007, 542pp, $38.95 HB, $28.95 PB

  • Book Symposium
  • Published:
Metascience Aims and scope

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. Cf., for a different orientation on the modern, post-nineteenth-century scientist, Shapin (2008).

  2. I shall say nothing about the fascinating chapter, “Trained Judgment”, but allow myself a comment on the paradigm picture, fig. 1.3, which is also reproduced as the first colored plate at the end of the book, and which is a detail of fig. 6.10, which is there called a “magnetogram of the sun”. The description under fig. 1.3 is: “This image of the magnetic field of the sun mixed the output of sophisticated equipment with a ‘subjective’ smoothing of the data—the authors deemed this intervention necessary to remove instrumental artifacts.” Pedantry calls: (1.3) is not an “image of the magnetic field of the sun”, it is a chart (as the authors of the chart call it) of the changes in the magnetic field of the sun during 6 days in August, 1959. And (6.10) is not a “magnetogram of the sun”, but a visual summary of data derived from a series of solar magnetograms (images of magnetic field distributions) obtained in Pasadena, Los Angeles, during one rotation of the sun’s equator, of which the 6 days of (1.3) form the first part. Indeed, (1.3) is the beginning of the longest continuous record of observed magnetic fields of the sun (using the Zeeman Effect); it still continues in Pasadena, although now one may prefer to watch online the minute-by-minute results of the SOHO satellite (Solar and Heliospheric Observatory). The authors at the Mount Wilson Observatory published numerous sophisticated discussions of reliability and of difficulties that are far more intense than removing “instrumental artifacts”. There are at least a dozen kinds of technical difficulty—this is the first time the apparatus has been up and running—and the issue is not ‘smoothing’. For a popular discussion, see Bumba and Howard (1965a); otherwise Babcock (1953), Howard and Babcock (1960), Bumba and Howard (1965b). The use of the adjectives “subjective”, “objective”, and “reliable” in these texts is a model of clarity. These remarks in no way conflict with D&G’s use of the chart, but point to a complex story in its own right.

  3. Michel Foucault, whom I am co-opting here, always included diagrams and other pictorial inscriptions among the énoncés, the “statements” that serve as data.

  4. Beck (1969, p. 284). The locus classicus for this assertion is Eucken (1879, p. 134). Prantl (1855, p. 145) asserts that the French theologian Jean Charlier de Gerson (1363–1429) foreshadowed the transition. D&G note 9, (p. 422), mention recent studies of the words before Kant, but as is often the case, those tireless German scholars of the nineteenth century did it best.

  5. Kritik der praktischen Vernunft, 1788, Part I, Book I, Chapter 1, §1, as translated by Beck (1949).

  6. de Staël (1958). The first print run (10,000 copies!) of 1810 was suppressed by Bonaparte’s administration.

  7. Cited in Ashton (1977).

  8. From the English translation, London: John Murray, 1814, as reprinted in de Staël-Holstein (1862, p. 162). de Staël (1958), vol. 4, 123–124.

  9. From Huxley’s notebook, begun in 1840. D&G, p. 214. The entry is dated January 30, 1842.

  10. The problem, as stated by Whewell, is precisely the problem that Bertrand Russell sought to resolve (or dismiss) in three rather isolated, and rather sarcastic, pages in his Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy, written from jail and published 1919 (Russell 1924, pp. 60–62), and cited by D&G, pp. 293–295 in their chapter on structural objectivity. Russell uses the concept of structure (half the time in quotation marks) to show how the notions of “a phenomenal world” (supposedly subjective), and of “a world behind the phenomena” (supposedly objective), if they have any sense at all, must have the same structure. Hence, most of the philosophical debates about Appearance and Reality collapse. Whewell might not have assented to the argument, but he would have well understood what Russell was up to.

  11. Whewell (1847, p. 318), footnote. At that time, the best place to go in English for a historical account of the meanings of objective/subjective was a real Kantian, namely Sir William Hamilton (Hamilton 1846, pp. 806–809).

References

  • Anscombe, Elizabeth, and Peter Thomas Geach eds. 1954. Descartes: Philosophical writings. London: Nelson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashton, Rosemary D. 1977. Coleridge and Faust. The Review of English Studies 28: 156–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Babcock, Horace W. 1953. The solar magnetograph. Astrophysical Journal 118: 387–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beck, Lewis White. 1949. Critique of practical reason and other writings in moral philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beck, Lewis White. 1969. Early German philosophy: Kant and his predecessors. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bumba, V., and Robert Howard. 1965a. Solar magnetic fields. Science 149: 1331–1337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bumba, V., and Robert Howard. 1965b. A study of the development of active regions on the sun. Astrophysical Journal 141: 1492–1501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daston, Lorraine, and Peter Galison. 1992. The image of objectivity. Representations 40: 81–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Certeau, Michel. 1974. L’opération historique. In Faire de l’histoire. J. Le Goff and P. Nora eds., 3–41. Paris.

  • de Staël, Anne Louise Germaine. 1958. De l’Allemagne. [Nouvelle édition d’après les manuscrits et les éditions originales avec des variantes.]. Jean de Pange and Simone Balayé, 5 vols. Paris: Hachette.

  • de Staël-Holstein, Anne Louise Germaine. 1862. Germany. Ed. O. W. Wright. New York: Derby and Jackson, vol. 2.

  • Eucken, Rudolf. 1879. Geschichte der philosophischen Terminologie in Umriss dargestellt. Leipzig. Repr. Hildesheim: Olm. 1960.

  • Foucault, Michel. 1994. Dits et écrits. Paris, vol. 1.

  • Galison, Peter. 1997. Image and logic: A material culture of microphysics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gooday, Graeme. 1991. ‘Nature’ in the laboratory: Domestication and discipline with the microscope in Victorian life science. British Journal for the History of Science 24: 307–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, William ed. 1846. The works of Thomas Reid. Edinburgh: McLaghlan Stewart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, Robert, and Horace W. Babcock. 1960. Magnetic fields associated with the solar flare of July. Astrophysical Journal 132: 218–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prantl, Carl. 1855. Geschichte der Logik im Abendlande, 4 vols. Leipzig. Repr. Graz: Akademische Druck. 1955, vol. IV.

  • Russell, Bertrand. 1924. Introduction to mathematical philosophy, 2nd ed. London: Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, Steven. 2008. The scientific life: A moral history of a late modern vocation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whewell, William. 1847. The philosophy of the inductive sciences, founded upon their history, vol. II, 2nd ed. London: Parker.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter Dear.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Dear, P., Hacking, I., Jones, M.L. et al. Objectivity in historical perspective. Metascience 21, 11–39 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11016-011-9597-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11016-011-9597-2

Navigation