Skip to main content
Log in

The co-consciousness hypothesis

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Self-knowledge seems to be radically different from the knowledge of other people. However, rather than focusing on the gap between self and others, we should emphasize their commonality. Indeed, different “mirror matching mechanisms” have been found in monkeys as well as in humans showing that one uses the same representations for oneself and for the others. But do these shared representations allow one to report the mental states of others as if they were one's own? I intend in this essay to address the epistemic problem of other minds by developing Ayer's notion of co-consciousness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Adams, F. 2001. Empathy, neural imaging and the theory versus simulation debate. Mind and Language 16(4): 368-392.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, A. J. 1963. Privacy. In: The Concept of a Person and Other Essays, pp. 52-81. New York: St Martin's Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S. 1997. Mindblindness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calder, J. A., Keane, J., Manes, F., Antoun, N. and Young, A. W. 2000. Impaired recognition and experience of disgust following brain injury. Nature Neuroscience 3(11): 1077-1078.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, L., Iacoboni, M., Dubeau, M. C., Maziotta, J. C. and Lenzi, G. L. 2003. Neural mechanisms of empathy in humans: A relay from neural systems for imitation in limbic areas. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 100(9): 5497-502.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. R. 1999. The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness. New York: Harcourt Brace and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. 1987. Knowing one's own mind. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, pp. 441-458.

  • de Vignemont, F. and Fourneret, P. 2004. The sense of agency: A philosophical and empirical review of the 'Who' system. Consciousness and Cognition 13(1): 1-19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Decety, J., Grèzes, J., Costes, N., Perani, D. and Jeannerod, M. 1997. Brain activity during observation of action content and subject's strategy. Brain 120: 1763-1777.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. 1641/1960. Méditations Métaphysiques. Paris: PUF.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eisenberg, N. and Strayer, J. 1987. Empathy and Its Development. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C. D., Blakemore, S. and Wolpert, D. 2000. Abnormalities in the awareness and control of action. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London 355: 1771-1788.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 2001. The practice of the mind. Theory, simulation or primary interaction? Journal of Consciousness Studies 5–7: 83-108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. and Goldman, A. I. 1998. Mirror neurons and the simulation theory of mind-reading. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 2: 493-501.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. 2000. The acting subject: Towards the neural basis of social cognition. In: T. Metzinger (ed), Neural Correlates of Consciousness: Empirical and Conceptual Questions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. 2001. The 'shared Manifold' Hypothesis: From mirror neurons to empathy. Journal of Consciousness Studies 8(5–7): 33-50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. 2003. The manifold nature of interpersonal relations: The quest for a common mechanism. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, Series B 358: 517-528.

    Google Scholar 

  • Georgieff, N. and Jeannerod, M. 1998. Beyond consciousness of external reality: A “Who” system for consciousness of action and self-consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition 7: 465-477.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. 1992. Empathy, mind and morals. Proceedings and Addresses of the APA 66: 3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. 1993a. Consciousness, folk psychology and cognitive science. Consciousness and Cognition 2: 364-382.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. 1993b. The psychology of folk psychology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16: 15-28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. 2002. Simulation theory and mental concepts. In: J. Dokic and J. Proust (eds), Simulation and Knowledge of Action, Advances in Consciousness Research, 45.

  • Gopnik, A. and Astington, J. W. 1988. Children's understanding of representational change and its relation to the understanding of the false belief and the appearance — reality distinction. Child Development 59(1): 27-37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A. 1993. How we know our minds: The illusion of first-person knowledge of intentionality. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16: 1-14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A. and Meltzoff 1994. Minds, bodies and persons: Young children's understanding of the self and others as reflected in imitation and “theory of mind” research. In: S. Parker and R. Mitchell (eds), Self-Awareness in Animals and Humans. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, R. M. 1996. Simulation without introspection or inference from me to you. In: P. Carruthers and P. Smith (eds), Theories of Theories of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, P. 1989. Children and Emotion. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchison, W. D. 1999. Pain related neurons in the human cingulate cortex. Nature Neuroscience 2: 403-405.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. 1986. What Mary didn't know. The Journal of Philosophy LXXXIII(5): 291-295.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M. 1994. The representing brain: Neural correlates of motor intention and imagery. Behavioral Brain Sciences 17: 187-245.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M. K., Hashtroudi, S. and Lindsay, D. S. 1993. Source monitoring. Psychological Bulletin 114: 3-28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett, R. E. and Wilson, T. D. 1977. Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review 84: 231-259.

    Google Scholar 

  • Preston, S. D. and de Waal, F. B. M. 2002. Empathy: Its ultimate and proximate bases. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25(1): 1-20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramachandran, V. S. and Hirstein, W. 1997. Three laws of qualia: What neurology tells us about the biological functions of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 4: 429-457.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ravenscroft, I. 1998. What is it like to be someone else? Simulation and empathy. Ratio XI: 170-185.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L., Gallese, V. and Fogassi, L. 1996. Premotor cortex and the recognition of motor actions. Cognitive Brain Research 3: 131-141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. 1966. Self-Knowledge. Reprinted, 1994. In: Q. Cassam (ed), Self-Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. 1984. Self-reference and self-awareness. In: Identity, Cause and Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimmer, H. and Perner, J. 1983. Beliefs about beliefs: Representation and constraining function of wrong beliefs in youg children's understanding of deception. Cognition 13(1): 103-128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wispé, L. 1986. The distinction between sympathy and empathy: To call forth a concept, a word is needed. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 50(2): 314-321.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

de Vignemont, F. The co-consciousness hypothesis. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 3, 97–114 (2004). https://doi.org/10.1023/B:PHEN.0000041894.48541.1c

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/B:PHEN.0000041894.48541.1c

Navigation