Skip to main content
Log in

Styles of Rejection in Local Public Argument on Iraq

  • Published:
Argumentation Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A campaign to pass city council resolutions opposing an American invasion of Iraq in the Fall of 2002 and Spring of 2003 provided an opportunity to examine contrasting styles of public argument. This paper examines an extensive set of news and editorial articles as well as the actual deliberations before city councils. An argument’s style constructs a relationship between the speaker, audience, and issue through the strategic use of language. Two conflicting styles of argument were apparent in these deliberations: a protest style and a dissent style. Each style operated within a different normative frame that managed tensions between unity and division, participation and its lack, and inclusive and exclusive reasoning. While protest and dissent styles conflict, each frames important relationships for public discourse and deliberation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Many subtle and not so subtle differences in the perspectives of these theorists, notably Dryzek, Young, Mouffe, and Hauser, have been set aside in this gloss. However, despite significant theoretical differences, each of these theorists has identified the tensions these three norms place on the practice of democracy and argues, albeit by different means, for practices that manage division, garner participation, and apply reasoned argument to the problems and issues faced by diverse interests.

  2. This figure was arrived at by searching the Lexis-Nexis database by U.S. region for articles containing the words Iraq, resolution, and city council between September 1, 2002 and September 1, 2003 in the Spring of 2004. All irrelevant and duplicate articles were removed from the corpus and are not included in the final number.

  3. Each style and entailing element was apparent in the discourse through frequent appearance in both spoken and written discourse. No attempt has been made in this analysis to quantify the relative frequency or extensiveness of the styles or their elements, nor examine the rate of occurrence in different media and contexts. While future studies may examine these aspects of the styles, this study’s purpose is to explicate the styles and their features.

  4. The protest style identified adopts a set of norms similar to those which Young (2001) identified with activists. Rather than label the protest style as “activist,” each style has been examined only in terms of rejection. Activists and deliberators do more than reject positions. It is possible that the dissent style and protest style each align with the deliberative and activist roles Young has outlined, but that should be indicated by examining styles of both rejection and acceptance.

  5. Although the resolution speakers were advocating a position (passing a resolution is a positive act), they framed their discourse, universally, as an opposition to the Administration’s supposed, and later declared, actions. This is also why I term their campaign and resolutions “anti-war” rather than “peace;” their position was essentially oppositional.

  6. It is important to note that resolution proponents were not the only people utilizing what I term intentional incivility. Many “pro-war” speakers utilized a similar style when arguing in favor of the administration or the war and against resolutions or their proponents. This form of action I would term “propaganda,” but will not address in this paper.

  7. Dissoi Logoi refers to the principle of two-sided argument. In the work of Protagoras (see Sloane 2001) and the treatise “Dissoi Logoi” (see Dissoi Logoi 2001), the principle explains that any issue can be argued from two different sides. The rhetorician’s purpose is to develop each side and determine which is the stronger. The U.S. court system works on this principle. As an aspect of dissent style, it refers to the idea that those dissenting acknowledge that there are opposing arguments assenting and that the stronger of the two, whichever that happens to be, ought to prevail. This implies that a one-sided debate and decisions that do not take into account opposing viewpoints are illegitimate.

  8. Like any governing body, the deliberation that occurs in the meeting itself may not be what has determined the positions of the various parties. Like the town hall meetings in Mansbridge’s (1980) “Selby,” the decision itself may be made outside the forum, but the forum is where the public display of deliberation—justifying and criticizing the options—takes place.

  9. Transcribed council sessions use Jeffersonian notation common in the discourse analytic tradition (see Hutchby and Woffitt 1998). Speakers are transcribed exactly as they sounded, so that false starts, self repairs, and pronunciation is captured as the spoken words sounded. This should not reflect negatively on the speakers; lack of grammatical coherence is typical in spoken discourse. Some common notations are: pauses (numbers in parentheses used for length in seconds, period in parentheses used for less than 1 s); words in parentheses represent a best guess as to what was said; empty parentheses indicate an unidentifiable sound; colons indicate stretched sound; underlining indicates emphasis; and capitalization indicates louder volume.

  10. In social interaction a repair is a conversational move that reforms a previous utterance. It can be self initiated, where the speaker initiates the repair or other initiated where the interlocutor either initiates a call to repair or reformulates the speaker’s statement (Hutchby and Woffitt 1998). Since public conversation works according to many of the same principles, this reprimand serves as an other-initiated repair.

  11. It is not my intention to imply that ad hominem arguments are necessarily fallacious. Attacks on the source of a position may be relevant to discourse in many circumstances (see Brinton 1995).

  12. van Eemeren et al. (1993) approach argument in ways that provide a theoretical basis for this connection between interaction and public reason. The principles of socialization and externalization, particularly, provide an account of the interactive aspects of argument and the way arguments construct both a standpoint and the potential for opposition to that standpoint.

  13. For instance, in the Denver City Council meeting a resolution opponent argued that he found it “mysterious” that the resolution called for further deliberation and proceeded to recount the deliberative proceedings leading up to the current war. Similar sentiments were expressed by a Boulder councilman who opposed council action with respect to the war.

  14. Slippery slope designates a logically fallacy whereby a claim is refuted due to what it will lead to rather than its own merits. It is important to note that, like other aspects of style, this form of argument does not reflect upon the truthfulness of the claim. This form of argument is used in cases of domestic violence, where one dominating behavior often leads to greater and greater transgressions. As an old proverb states, an avalanche begins with the falling of a single stone.

  15. figure g
  16. This is similar to Hariman and Lucaties (2001) analysis of the iconic Kent State photograph, where the viewer is called upon to respond to the dramatic emotion displayed in the photograph. Here however, there is still the descriptive drama, but the verbal image gains its power through the “witness” displaying the scene, rather than iconic status.

  17. The discourse has a reciprocal relationship to the relationship among interlocutors. It constructs the relationship, based on the relational definitions available, but can also change that relational definition by representing the relationship in a different way. In this way it is both constructive and reflective of the relationship. For simplicity I use construction for both since construction must be out of something as well as of something.

References

  • Anderson, P.A., and T.R. Blackburn. 2004. An experimental study of language intensity and response rate in e mail surveys. Communication Reports 17: 73–84.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asen, R. 2004. A discourse theory of citizenship. Quarterly Journal of Speech 90: 189–211.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J.L. 1999. How to do things with words. In The discourse reader, ed. A. Jaworski, and N. Coupland, 63–75. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barge, J.K., and J. Keyton. 1994. Contextualizing power and social influence in groups. In Group communication in context: Studies of natural groups, ed. L.R. Frey, 85–105. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beasley, V.B. 2008. Democratic style: An RSVP. Rhetoric and Public Affairs 11: 466–470.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bilder, R.B. 1989. The role of states and cities in foreign relations. American Journal of International Law 83: 821–831.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Black, E. 1978. Rhetorical criticism: A study in method. Madison: University of Wisconsion Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowers, J.W. 1963. Language intensity, social introversion, and attitude change. Speech Monographs 30: 345–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowers, J.W., D.J. Ochs, et al. 1993. The rhetoric of agitation and control. Prospect Heights: Waveland Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brinton, A. 1995. The Ad Hominem. In Fallacies: Classical, contemporary readings, ed. H.V. Hansen, and R.C. Pinto, 213–222. University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chambers, S. 2003. Deliberative democratic theory. Annual Review of Political Science 6: 307–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, R. 1983. Galilean rhetoric and practical theory. Communication Monographs 50: 395–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, R.T., and K. Tracy. 2003. ‘The issue’ in argumentation practice and theory. In The Fifth Conference of the International Society for the Study of Argumentation, International Center for the Study of Argumentation, eds. van Eemeren F.H., Blair J.A, Willard C.A., and Henkemans A.F.S, 213–218.

  • Craig, R.T., and K. Tracy. 1995. Grounded practical theory: The case of intellectual discussion. Communication Theory 5: 248–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cronen, V.E. 2001. Practical theory, practical art, and the pragmatic-systemic account of inquiry. Communication Theory 11: 14–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Delicath, J.W., and K.M. DeLuca. 2003. Image events, the public sphere, and argumentative practice: The case of radical environmental groups. Argumentation 17: 315–334.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeLuca, K.M. 1999. Unruly arguments: The body rhetoric of Earth First!, Act Up, and Queer Nation. Argumentation and Advocacy 36: 9–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeVito, J.A. 1967. Style and stylistics: An attempt at definition. The Quarterly Journal of Speech 53: 248–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dimock, A. (2009). Creating sites for reasonable discourse: Stasis in public deliberation. Speaker and Gavel.

  • Dissoi Logoi. 2001. In The rhetorical tradition: Readings from classical times to the present (trans: Robinson, T. M.), ed. P. Bizzell and B. Herzberg, 48–55. New York: Bedford/St. Martin's.

  • Dryzek, J.S. 1990. Discursive democracy: Politics, policy, and political science. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dryzek, J.S. 2001. Legitimacy and economy in deliberative democracy. Political Theory 29: 651–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dryzek, J.S. 2005. Deliberative democracy in divided societies: Alternatives to agonism and analgesia. Political Theory 33: 218–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eliasoph, N. 1998. Avoiding politics: How Americans produce apathy in everyday life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Engels, J. 2008. Some preliminary thoughts on democratic style. Rhetoric and Public Affairs 11: 439–440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, J.B. 1995. The appeal to popularity and presumption by common knowledge. In Fallacies: Classical, contemporary readings, ed. H.V. Hansen, and R.C. Pinto, 265–273. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gastil, J. 1992. Undemocratic discourse: A review of theory and research on political discourse. Discourse and Society 3: 469–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H.P. 1999. Logic and conversation. In The discourse reader, ed. A. Jaworski, and N. Coupland, 77–88. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gutmann, A. 1993. The disharmony of democracy. In NOMOS XXXV, ed. J.W. Chapman, and I. Shapiro, 126–160. New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gutmann, A. 1995. The virtues of democratic self constraint. In New communitarian thinking: Persons, virtues, institutions, and communities, ed. A. Etzioni, 155–169. Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, M.A., and B.L. Stewart. 1993. Extending an information processing model of language intensity effects. Communication Quarterly 41: 231–246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hariman, R. 1995. Political style: The artistry of power. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hariman, R. 1999. Aversion to and a version of the democratic aesthetic. In Argument at century’s end: Reflecting on the past, envisioning the future, ed. T.A. Hollihan, 286–293. Alta: National Communication Association/American Forensic Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hariman, R., and J.L. Lucaties. 2001. Dissent and emotional management in a liberal democratic society: The Kent State iconic photograph. Rhetorical Society Quarterly 31: 4–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, G. 1999. Vernacular voices: The rhetoric of publics and public spheres. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, G., and C. Benoit-Barne. 2002. Reflections on rhetoric, deliberative democracy, civil society and trust. Rhetoric and Public Affairs 5: 261–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heidlebaugh, N.J. 2001. Judgment, rhetoric, and the problem of incommensurability: Recalling practical wisdom. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hibbing, J., and E. Theiss-Morse. 2002. Stealth democracy: American’s beliefs about how government should work. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hicks, D. 2002. The promise(s) of deliberative democracy. Rhetoric and Public Affairs 5: 223–260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hofstadter, R. 1965. The paranoid style in American politics. In The paranoid style in American politics and other essays, 3–40, New York: Alfred A Knopf.

  • Hutchby, I., and R. Woffitt. 1998. Conversation analysis. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ivie, R.L. 2002. Rhetorical deliberation and democratic politics in the here and now. Rhetoric and Public Affairs 5: 277–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ivie, R.L. 2008. Toward a humanizing style of democratic dissent. Rhetoric and Public Affairs 11: 454–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, S., and S. Jacobs. 1980. Structure of conversational argument. Quarterly Journal of Speech 66: 251–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jorgensen, C. 1998. Public debate – an act of hostility? Argumentation 12: 431–443.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karpowitz, C.F. 2005. A theory of local public talk and deliberative reform. Washington, DC: American Political Science Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keith, W. 2002. Democratic revival and the promise of cyberspace: Lessons from the forum movement. Rhetoric and Public Affairs 5: 311–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kline, S.L. 1979. Toward a contemporary linguistic interpretation of the concept of stasis. Journal of the American Forensic Association 16: 95–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Low, D.W. 1996. The greenie genre: Noble saviours or planetary fools. Australian Journal of Communication 23: 101–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maddux, K. 2004. When patriots protest: The anti-suffrage discursive transformation of 1917. Rhetoric and Public Affairs 7: 283–310.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mansbridge, J. 1980. Beyond adversary democracy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mattson, K. 2002. Do Americans really want deliberative democracy? Rhetoric and Public Affairs 5: 327–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McComas, K.A. 2000. Theory and practice of public meetings. Cornell University (Unpublished dissertation).

  • Mendelberg, T., and J. Oleske. 2000. Race and public deliberation. Political Communication 17: 169–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mouffe, C. 1999. Deliberative democracy or agonistic pluralism? Social Research 66: 745–758.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mouffe, C. 2000. The democratic paradox. New York: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nock, C.J. 1995. On the dissent theory of political obligation. Polity 28: 141–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pellizzoni, L. 2001. The myth of the best argument: Power, deliberation and reason. British Journal of Sociology 52: 59–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plein, L.C., K.E. Green, and D.G. Williams. 1998. Organic planning: A new approach to public participation in local governance. The Social Science Journal 35: 509–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pomerantz, A. 1986. Extreme case formulations: A way of legitimizing claims. Human Studies 9: 219–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price, D. 2000. Choices without reasons: Citizens’ juries and policy evaluation. Journal of Medical Ethics 26: 272–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1997/1999. The idea of public reason revisited, In John Rawls: Collected papers, ed. S. Freeman, 573–615. Cambridge: Harvard University Press

  • Rogan, R.G. 1995. Language intensity: Testing a content-based metric. Communication Reports 8: 128–135.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryfe, D.M. 2002. The practice of deliberative democracy: A study of 16 deliberative organizations. Political Communication 19: 359–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scarry, E. 2004. Acts of resistance. Harper’s magazine, May: 15–20.

  • Sharp, E.B. 2005. Morality politics in American cities. Lawrence, KS: University of Kansas Press.

  • Shuman, M. H. 1992. Dateline main street: Courts v. local foreign policies. Foreign Policy 86: 158–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shuman, M.H. 1998. Protecting the local globally, In American political science association annual meeting, vol 56. Boston.

  • Sloane, T.O. (ed.). 2001. Encyclopedia of rhetoric. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stamou, A.G. 2001. The representation of non-protesters in a student and teacher protest: A critical discourse analysis of news reporting in a Greek newspaper. Discourse and Society 12: 653–680.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tracy, K. 1995. Action-implicative discourse analysis. Journal of Language and Social Psychology 14: 195–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tracy, K. 1999. The usefulness of platitudes in arguments about conduct. Paper presented at the fourth international conference of the interactional society for the study of argumentation, Amsterdam.

  • Tracy, K. 2008. ‘Reasonable hostility’: Situation-appropriate face-attack. Journal of Politeness Research: Language, Behavior, Culture 4: 169–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tracy, K., and C. Ashcraft. 2001. Crafting policies about controversial values: How wording disputes manage a group dilemma. Journal of Applied Communication 29: 297–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tracy, K., and A. Dimock. 2004. Meetings: Discursive sites for building and fragmenting community. Communication Yearbook 28: 127–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tracy, K., and C. Standerfer. 2003. Selecting a school superintendent: Sensitivities in group deliberation. In Group communication in context: Studies of natural groups, 2nd ed, ed. L. Frey, 109–134. Mahwah: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F.H., and R. Grootendorst. 1995. The pragma-dialectical approach to fallacies. Fallacies: Classical and contemporary readings. In Hans V. Hansen, and Robert C. Pinto, 130–144. Pennsylvania: University Park, Pennsylvania State University Press.

  • van Eemeren, F.H., R. Grootendorst, S. Jackson, and S. Jacobs. 1993. Reconstructing argumentative discourse. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ware, B.L., and W.A. Linkugel. 1973. They spoke in defense of themselves: On the generic criticism of apologia. Quarterly Journal of Speech 59: 273–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Welsh, S. 2002. Deliberative democracy and the rhetorical production of political culture. Rhetoric and Public Affairs 5: 679–708.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, I.M. 2001. Activist challenges to deliberative democracy. Political Theory 29: 670–690.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Aaron Dimock.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Dimock, A. Styles of Rejection in Local Public Argument on Iraq. Argumentation 24, 423–452 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-009-9175-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-009-9175-6

Keywords

Navigation