Skip to main content
Log in

Grades of individuality. A pluralistic view of identity in quantum mechanics and in the sciences

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper offers a critical assessment of the current state of the debate about the identity and individuality of material objects. Its main aim, in particular, is to show that, in a sense to be carefully specified, the opposition between the Leibnizian ‘reductionist’ tradition, based on discernibility, and the sort of ‘primitivism’ that denies that facts of identity and individuality must be analysable has become outdated. In particular, it is argued that—contrary to a widespread consensus—‘naturalised’ metaphysics supports both the acceptability of non-qualitatively grounded (both ‘contextual’ and intrinsic) identity and a pluralistic approach to individuality and individuation. A case study is offered that focuses on non-relativistic quantum mechanics, in the context of which primitivism about identity and individuality, rather than being regarded as unscientific, is on the contrary suggested to be preferable to the complicated forms of reductionism that have recently been proposed. More generally, by assuming a plausible form of anti-reductionism about scientific theories and domains, it is claimed that science can be regarded as compatible with, or even as suggesting, the existence of a series of equally plausible grades of individuality. The kind of individuality that prevails in a certain context and at a given level can be ascertained only on the basis of the specific scientific theory at hand.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There is, of course, also an important connection with the work of Quine (1960, 1976). On the basis of ideas of Hilbert and Bernays, Quine showed that (provided that the vocabulary of non-analysed general terms is finite) the identity sign can be paraphrased away in any first-order language, and replaced with a conjunction of non-identity-involving formulas (in particular, conditionals of the form ‘if Fx then Fy’ for any x and y and any number of places in F). This must be mentioned, as authors that we will discuss later on worked in an explicitly Quinean setting.

  2. For PII as an analytical truth, see Whitehead and Russell (1925, p. 57), Church (1956, p. 302) and Brody (1980, pp. 6–9).

  3. For a defence of this claim, see Black (1952, p. 155), Ayer (1954, p. 29), Katz (1983), and Rodriguez-Pereyra (2006).

  4. And by no means limited to historical figures in philosophy: for the influence of Schopenhauer’s view of space on Einstein’s thoughts on separability, for instance, see Howard (1997).

  5. It could be objected that Black doesn’t explicitly rule out the existence of an absolute spatial background. This exegetical point, however, doesn’t affect the strength of the counterexample: the location occupied by each sphere must in any case be described in absolutely general terms, turning out to be the same for the two spheres.

  6. Black’s argument might be rejected as question-begging (as in, for example, Odegard (1964)) or as re-describable in reductionist terms (as in Hacking (1975)). But the former objection has no force here, as we are looking for a justification of PII in the first place. With respect to the latter, it must be noticed instead that a re-description may not always be available, and Hacking’s strategy might in any case not be regarded as a legitimate reductionist response. An ‘extreme’ option is to follow O’Leary-Hawthorne (1995) in claiming that in Black’s universe there is only one sphere at some distance from itself, but this really looks like a last resort for the defender of PII, especially from a naturalistic viewpoint.

  7. We are grateful to an anonymous referee for pressing us on this point concerning mathematical as opposed to physical ontology.

  8. In other words, haecceitism and the view that individuals (may) possess haecceitates are distinct and largely independent theses.

  9. Remember our distinction above between two ways of understanding naturalism.

  10. French and Redhead’s results have been later improved upon by Butterfield (1993) and Huggett (2003).

  11. In particular, Muller and Saunders use only spin degrees of freedom (specifically, total spin relations) in finite Hilbert spaces; and more general commutator relations holding between distinct single-particle operators (e.g., position and momentum) in the case of infinite-dimensional Hilbert spaces.

  12. We do not attribute this presupposition to MSS themselves because they seem quite neutral on this. In fact, what they say seems best interpreted as motivated by the idea that the question whether physical objects can adequately be described using PII is an interesting one in itself.

  13. Notice, in this connection, that a reductionist viewpoint seems to be shared also by authors who disagree with MSS. For instance, Dieks and Versteegh (2008) conclude their critique of MSS by arguing that one should opt for a holistic interpretation of quantum systems of identical particles (i.e., one where the total system simply has no component particles) (compare Hawley’s (2009) ‘summing defence’ of PII). This clearly suggests that Dieks and Versteegh too reject primitivism as unscientific.

  14. Interestingly, Ladyman and Bigaj (2010, p. 135) express ideas similar to ours when they suggest that perhaps “anything that is the value of a first-order variable is an individual” , but do not emphasise the role played by countability assumptions in the arguments in favour of the weak discernibility of quantum particles.

  15. For an interesting defence of a neo-Nagelian account of reduction, see for example Dizadji-Bahmani, Frigg and Hartmann (2010). Another account of reduction, in terms of asymptotic behaviour, is spelled out by Batterman (2002).

  16. For instance, to the effect that quantum field theory is in general more empirically adequate than quantum mechanics.

  17. We are grateful to an anonymous referee for pressing us on this point.

References

  • Adams, R. M. (1979). Primitive thisness and primitive identity. Journal of Philosophy, 76, 5–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, A. J. (1954). The identity of the indiscernibles, in philosophical essays. London: MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. W. (2002). The devil in the details. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brody, B. (1980). Identity and essence. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Black, M. (1952). The identity of indiscernibles. Mind, 61, 153–164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butterfield, J. (1989). The hole truth. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 40, 1–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfield, J. (1993). Interpretation and identity in quantum theory. Studies in history and Philosophy of Science, 24, 443–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Church, A. (1956). Introduction to mathematical logic (Vol. I). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daumer, M., Dürr, D., Goldstein, S., & Zanghì, N. (1996). Naïve realism about operators. Erkenntnis, 45, 379–397.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dieks, D., & Versteegh, M. (2008). Identical quantum particles and weak discernibility. Foundations of Physics, 38, 923–934.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dizadji-Bahmani, F., Frigg, R., & Hartmann, S. (2010). Who’s afraid of nagelian reduction? Erkenntnis, 73, 393–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dorato, M., & Pauri, M. (2006). Holism and structuralism in classical and quantum general relativity. In D. Rickles, S. French, & J. Saatsi (Eds.), Structural foundations of quantum gravity (pp. 121–151). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J., & Norton, J. D. (1987). What price space-time substantivalism. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 38, 515–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, S., & Redhead, M. (1988). Quantum mechanics and the identity of the indiscernibles. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 39, 233–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1975). The identity of indiscernibles. Journal of Philosophy, 72, 249–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K. (2009). Identity and indiscernibility. Mind, 118, 101–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howard, D. (1997). A peek behind the Veil of Maya: Einstein, Schopenhauer, and the historical background of the conception of space as a ground for the individuation of physical systems. In J. Earman & J. Norton (Eds.), The cosmos of science: Essays of exploration, Pittsburgh–Konstanz series in the philosophy and history of science (Vol. 6, pp. 87–150). Pittsburgh and Universitätsverlag, Konstanz: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huggett, N. (2003). Quarticles and the identity of the indiscernibles. In K. Brading & E. Castellani (Eds.), Symmetries in physics: Philosophical reflections (pp. 239–249). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Katz, B. D. (1983). The identity of the indiscernibles revisited. Philosophical Studies, 44, 37–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (2007). Scientific structuralism: On the identity and diversity of objects in a structure. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume, 81, 23–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., & Bigaj, T. (2010). The principle of the identity of indiscernibles and quantum mechanics. Philosophy of Science, 77, 117–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morganti, M. (2009). Inherent properties and statistics with individual particles in quantum mechanics. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 40, 223–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muller, F. A., & Saunders, S. (2008). Discerning fermions. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 59, 499–548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muller, F. A., & Seevinck, M. P. (2009). Discerning elementary particles. Philosophy of Science., 76, 179–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Leary-Hawthorne, J. (1995). The bundle theory of substance and the identity of the indiscernibles. Analysis, 55, 191–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odegard, D. (1964). Indiscernibles. Philosophical Quarterly, 14, 204–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Post, H., (1963): Individuality in physics, in The Listener, 70, 534-537, reprinted in 1973 in Vedanta for East and West, 32, 14–22.

  • Quine, W.v. O. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.v. O. (1976). Grades of discriminability. Journal of Philosophy, 73, 113–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. (2006). How not to trivialise the identity of the indiscernibles. In P. F. Strawson & A. Chakrabarti (Eds.), Universals, concepts and qualities: New essays on the meaning of predicates (pp. 205–224). London: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, S. (2006). Are quantum particles objects? Analysis, 66, 52–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stachel, J. (1993). The meaning of general covariance. In J. Earman, A. Janis, G. Massey, & N. Rescher (Eds.), Philosophical problems of the internal and external worlds: Essays on the philosophy of Adolf Grünbaum (pp. 129–160). Pittsburgh and Universitätsverlag, Konstanz: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, A. N., & Russell, B. (1925). Principia mathematica (Vol. I). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matteo Morganti.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Dorato, M., Morganti, M. Grades of individuality. A pluralistic view of identity in quantum mechanics and in the sciences. Philos Stud 163, 591–610 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-011-9833-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-011-9833-z

Keywords

Navigation