Skip to main content
Log in

Parental partiality and the intergenerational transmission of advantage

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Parents typically favour their own children over others’. For example, most parents invest more time and money in their own children than in other children. This parental partiality is usually regarded as morally permissible, or even obligatory, but it can have undesirable distributive effects. For example, it may create unfair or otherwise undesirable advantages for the favoured child. A number of authors have found it necessary to justify parental partiality in the face of these distributive concerns, and they have typically done so by appealing to features of the parent–child relationship. Parental partiality is said to be justified, despite its undesirable distributive effects, in part because the parent enjoys a special kind of relationship with her child. In this paper, I raise a problem for such relational defences of parental partiality. I report empirical findings suggesting that parental partiality will frequently create advantages—sometimes undesirable—not only for one’s children, but also for one’s more distant descendants; I argue that the creation of these latter advantages stands as much in need of justification as does the creation of advantages for one’s own children; and I claim that existing relational defences do not clearly contain the resources necessary to deliver such a justification. I then examine three possible responses to this problem.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. On the effects of bedtime storytelling, see, for example, Hale et al. (2011), Bus et al. (1995) and Brighouse and Swift (2009) at notes 23 and 24.

  2. I henceforth often omit the qualifier ‘moral’.

  3. See, for discussion of this point, Kolodny (2002).

  4. For discussion of these latter cases, see Brighouse and Swift (2009), pp. 74–76.

  5. Pettit and Goodin (1986) defend a view with a similar structure.

  6. Further relational defences of parental or other varieties of partiality appear in, or might be grounded on, Brighouse and Swift (2009), Goodin (1988), Raz (1989), Hurka (1997), McMahan (1997), Scheffler (1997, 2001), Jeske (1998), Miller (2005), Kolodny (2010) and Stroud (2010).

  7. See, for a prominent example, Brighouse and Swift (2009).

  8. For example, Hertz et al. (2008) compared the USA and several European countries and found parent–child correlations for years of schooling in the range 0.30–0.54. Correlation coefficients for the USA and UK were 0.46 and 0.31 respectively. The correlation coefficient provides a measure of the degree of linear interdependence between two variables, for example, the earnings of parents and the earnings of their offspring. It always takes a value between −1 and +1 inclusive. The closer it is to −1 or +1, the stronger the correlation. A positive value indicates a positive correlation and a negative value indicates a negative one.

  9. The studies cited here have found correlation coefficients in the range 0.40–0.8 for the USA.

  10. This figure reduces to 4–5 % if the increase in parental education is taken as a single variable, without discriminating between maternal and paternal education.

  11. It might be thought that this burden of justification could be avoided by maintaining that transmitted advantages are unintended by parents who engage in parental partiality whereas first-generational advantages are not. [For an argument suggesting that this difference in intentions might be morally significant, see Segall (2011).] This response seems unpromising, however. We are addressing ourselves to those who concede that at least some first-generational advantages created through parental partiality require justification. But many of the first-generational advantages that most obviously call for justification are themselves typically unintended by the parents. Consider the undesirable social and educational advantages that may be created by sending one’s child to an elite private school. A parent might send her child to a private school intending that this will give her child a good education, and perhaps even intending that it will give her a better education than others, but without also intending that it will enable her to make more influential friends and outperform others in social situations requiring confidence, yet the latter advantages plausibly stand in need of justification.

  12. Brighouse and Swift treat the tendency to produce unfair inequality of opportunity as the primary problematic distributive effect of parental partiality, but I present their view in more general terms here.

  13. For example, they suggest that reading bedtime stories to one’s children and attending religious ceremonies or other community activities with them could often be justified by their account, whereas sending one’s child to an elite private school and investing in a trust fund for one’s child typically could not (2009, pp. 47–8, 56–8).

  14. At least, it seems plausible on the assumption that parent–child intimacy is an all-or-nothing affair. If parent–child intimacy is in fact a matter of degree, then we would need to reframe the question as one about how much parent–child intimacy is optimal.

  15. Brighouse and Swift (2009, p. 53) suggest a similar line of argument when they indicate that one relationship good that may help to justify parental partiality is that “[c]hildren enjoy a sense of continuity with (or belonging or attachment to) the past mediated by acquaintance with their own family members”.

  16. Similarly, Brighouse and Swift (2011, pp. 116–22) argue that maintaining positive national traditions is significantly less important than realising the sorts of relationship goods that characterise parent–child relationships.

  17. Though he does not use the term, Keller (2013) could be read as invoking agent-relative value (see also Sect. 2 above). He argues that your reasons to be partial towards your child derive from the value of your child, but that the value of your child generates reasons for you that it would not generate for others. Defences that appeal to the value of parental projects (for example, Williams 1982) plausibly also appeal to a value that is agent-relative: the value of our own projects plausibly generates stronger reasons for us than it does for others.

  18. Perhaps the clearest example of a fundamentally intimacy-based argument for parental partiality can be found in Jeske (1998). However Jeske’s argument would not, without amendment, fall within the scope of my critique in this paper, for it is not clearly intended as a response to concerns about undesirable advantages.

  19. This is something that many writers on partiality would take to be desirable regardless of whether they accept the argument in this paper. See, for example, Brighouse and Swift (2008, p. 145).

References

  • Belzil, C., & Hansen, J. (2003). ‘Structural estimates of the intergenerational education correlation. Journal of Applied Econometrics, 18, 679–696.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Black, S. E., & Devereux, P. J. (2011). Recent developments in intergenerational mobility. In O. C. Ashenfelter & D. Card (Eds.), Handbook of labor economics (Vol. 4, pp. 1487–1541). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brighouse, H., & Swift, A. (2006). Parents’ rights and the value of the family. Ethics, 117, 80–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brighouse, H., & Swift, A. (2008). Social justice and the family. In B. Craig, T. Burchardt, & D. Gordon (Eds.), Social justice and public policy (pp. 139–156). Bristol: The Policy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brighouse, H., & Swift, A. (2009). Legitimate parental partiality. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 37, 43–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brighouse, H., & Swift, A. (2011). Legitimate partiality, parents and patriots. In A. Gosseries & Y. Vanderborght (Eds.), Arguing about justice: Essays for Philippe Van Parijs (pp. 115–123). Louvain-la-Neuve: Presses universitaires de Louvain.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bus, A. G., van IJzendoorn, M. H., & Pellegrini, A. D. (1995). Joint book reading makes for success in learning to read: A meta-analysis on intergenerational transmission of literacy. Review of Educational Research, 65, 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chevalier, A. (2004). Parental education and child’s education: A natural experiment. Discussion Paper No. 1153. Bonn: Institute for the Study of Labor.

  • Cottingham, J. (1986). Partiality, favouritism and morality. Philosophical Quarterly, 36, 357–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dearden, L., Machin, S., & Reed, H. (1997). Intergenerational mobility in Britain. The Economic Journal, 107, 47–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R. (1988). What is so special about our fellow countrymen? Ethics, 98, 663–686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hale, L., Berger, L. M., LeBourgeois, M. K., & Brooks-Gunn, J. (2011). A longitudinal study of preschoolers’ language-based bedtime routines, sleep duration, and well-being. Journal of Family Psychology, 25, 423–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haveman, R., & Wolfe, B. (1995). The determinants of children’s attainments: A review of methods and findings. Journal of Economic Literature, 33, 1829–1878.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hertz, T., Jayasundera, T., Piraino, P., Selcuk, S., Smith, N., & Verashchagina, A. (2008). The inheritance of educational inequality: International comparisons and fifty-year trends. The B. E. Journal of Economic Analysis and Policy, 7 (article 10).

  • Hurka, T. (1997). The justification of national partiality. In R. McKim & J. McMahan (Eds.), The morality of nationalism (pp. 139–157). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeske, D. (1998). Families, friends, and special obligations. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 28(4), 527–555.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller, S. (2013). Partiality. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kolodny, N. (2002). Do associative duties matter? Journal of Political Philosophy, 10, 250–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kolodny, N. (2010). Which relationships justify partiality? The case of parents and children. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 38, 37–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMahan, J. (1997). The limits of national partiality. In R. McKim & J. McMahan (Eds.), The morality of nationalism (pp. 107–138). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (2005). Reasonable partiality towards compatriots. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 8, 63–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P., & Goodin, R. (1986). The possibility of special duties. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 16, 651–676.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1989). Liberating duties. Law and Philosophy, 8, 3–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sacerdote, B. (2007). How large are the effects from changes in family environment? A study of Korean American adoptees. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 122, 119–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler, S. (1997). Relationships and responsibilities. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 26, 189–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler, S. (2001). Boundaries and allegiances: Problems of justice and responsibility in liberal thought. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Segall, S. (2011). If you’re a luck egalitarian, how come you read bedtime stories to your children? Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 14(1), 23–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solon, G. (1999). Intergenerational mobility in the labor market. In O. C. Ashenfelter & D. Card (Eds.), Handbook of labor economics (Vol. 3, pp. 1761–1800). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stroud, S. (2010). Permissible partiality, projects, and plural agency. In B. Feltham & J. Cottingham (Eds.), Partiality and impartiality: morality, special relationships, and the wider world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1982). Persons, character and morality. In B. Williams (Ed.), Moral luck (pp. 1–19). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for Philosophical Studies, Harry Granqvist, Jacob Nebel, Saul Smilansky, and audiences in Bled (Slovenia) and Sheffield, for their comments on earlier versions of this paper; Adam Swift, for helpful discussions of his and Harry Brighouse's work on parental partiality; Simon Keller, for sharing an unpublished manuscript; and the Uehiro Foundation on Ethics and Education, for their financial support.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas Douglas.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Douglas, T. Parental partiality and the intergenerational transmission of advantage. Philos Stud 172, 2735–2756 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0442-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0442-0

Keywords

Navigation