Skip to main content

Pluralism in Logic: The Square of Opposition, Leibniz’ Principle of Sufficient Reason and Markov’s Principle

  • Chapter

Part of the book series: Studies in Universal Logic ((SUL))

Abstract

According to the present pluralism in mathematical logic, I translate from classical logic to non-classical logic the predicates of the classical square of opposition. A similar unique structure is obtained. In order to support this new logical structure, I investigate on the rich legacy of the non-classical arguments presented by ingenuity by several authors of scientific theories. A comparative analysis of their ways of arguing shows that each of these theories is severed in two parts; the former one proves a universal predicate by an ad absurdum proof. This conclusion of every theory results to be formalised by the A thesis of the new logical structure. Afterwards, this conclusion is changed in the corresponding affirmative predicate, which in the latter part plays the role of a new hypothesis for a deductive development. This kind of change is the same suggested by Leibniz’ principle of sufficient reason. Instead, Markov’s principle results to be a weaker logical change, from the intuitionist thesis I in the affirmative thesis I. The relevance of all the four theses of the new logical structure is obtained by studying all the conversion implications of intuitionist predicates. In the Appendix, I analyse as an example of the above theories, Markov’s presentation of his theory of real numbers.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The last instance of this qualification is the otherwise excellent text by [23].

  2. 2.

    I supported this view by the paper [11]. About the pluralism in science, see my paper [8].

  3. 3.

    Let us recall that the relationships of an affirmative proposition of propositional classical logic with the corresponding DNS of intuitionist logic is assured by a well-known theorem on their relationship—i.e. once a formula A is true in classical logic, then evenly ¬¬A is true in the latter logic. Instead, to translate a DNSs in an affirmative sentences, owing to the failure of the law of the double negation, is a problematic move [41, 56ff]. Notice also that in intuitionist logic an ad absurdum proof ends by a DNS; to change it in an affirmative sentence is allowed by classical logic only [18, p. 27].

  4. 4.

    [41, pp. 57–59]. In a previous paper [12] I introduced a square of opposition including at the same time two classical predicates (the theses A and E) and two non-classical predicates (the theses I and O) which differ from the traditional ones because the copula ‘is’ is changed in ‘it is not true that it is not’, or ‘is ’; this addition of double negations is not enough to represent one of the above-mentioned translations; however the results of the Sects. 7 and 8 of this paper agree with the above-mentioned translations.

  5. 5.

    According to modern logicians Aristotle’ square of opposition did not take in account the existential import of the theses. A more accurate investigation by authoritative scholars showed that instead Aristotle did it [33].

  6. 6.

    The same translations hold true for minimal predicate logic, i.e. when the logical law ex falso quodlibet (P→(¬P→Q), where P and Q are whatsoever predicates) is weakened in the law P→(¬P→¬Q), hence the latter logic is strictly weaker than intuitionist logic [41, p. 57]. One may guess that an experimental scientist is not allowed to deduce ex falso everything, included the true; but the false only; hence, his logic is the minimal one. In such a case the above translations in minimal predicate logic give distinct results from those in intuitionist logic when one claims that the copula “is” of a thesis of SO is better translated in logical terms by an equivalence, i.e. a double implication. In such a case the three translations of the theses of SO in minimal predicate logic are not equivalent in both E and I theses. However, according to the next footnote 18, the following results seem hold true for the minimal SO-like too even in the latter case.

  7. 7.

    Reference [25] lists 14 valid implications among couples of predicates. In the following an implication between two predicates will be denoted by putting in round bracket its number in the list of this section [18, p. 29].

  8. 8.

    In the past, this way of arguing joining together the DNSs was ignored. Rather some philosophers argued by considering at the same time the three values of a sole proposition A, i.e. A, ¬A and . Cusanus claimed to argue through an opposite’s coincidence of A and ; Hegel through an almost mechanical addiction of a negation to a sentence. See my paper [15].

  9. 9.

    It is by appealing to the past experiences of scientific theories that I improved the unsuccessful Beth’s research for a non-deductive way of organising a mathematical theory [2]. D’Alembert first stressed that there exists two kinds of theory organisation; he suggested that, beyond the “rational” kind, an “empirical” one exists [6]. Subsequently, for illustrating these two different models L. Carnot devoted two pages of each his two books on mechanics [3, 4]; he claimed to develop his theory in an “empirical” way. In past century both H. Poincaré [34, 35] and independently A. Einstein again suggested two similar kinds of theory organisation [27, 32].

  10. 10.

    Some of the above-mentioned authors wrote texts which are less structured in logical terms; e.g. L. Carnot’s calculus, Lavoisier’s chemistry, Galois’ theory of groups, Klein’s Erlangen program, Einstein’s theory of special relativity all lack of ad absurdum theorems.

  11. 11.

    [29]. Here and in the following, emphasis is added for manifesting to the reader the two negations within a doubly negated sentence.

  12. 12.

    [30, Proposition 19]. This book was analysed through its DNSs by my paper [14]. Lobachevsky’s main text puts the problem of how much parallel lines to a straight line exist. In order to obtain evidence for his guess—i.e. two parallel lines—he proves through DNSs five theorems, most of which are ad absurdum theorems. At the end of the prop. 22, shown by an ad absurdum theorem, he concludes that his supposition with respect to Euclid’s hypothesis, receives an equivalent evidence in both all points and in all figures in the space.

  13. 13.

    [5, p. 23]. S. Carnot’s thermodynamics puts the problem of the maximum efficiency in the heat/work conversions; in order to solve it, he looks for a new method by arguing through DNSs about his celebrated cycle of four transformations. The list of DNSs ends by means of his well-known ad absurdum theorem about the maximum efficiency in all heat/work conversions. Carnot’s book was analysed through its DNSs by the paper [17].

  14. 14.

    [36, p. 187]. Poincaré criticism to Formalists’ attempt to prove by finitist means the principle of mathematical induction concludes by essentially the following DNS: “… does not exist contradiction” for all entire numbers. The current version of this principle changes it in the corresponding affirmative predicate. See my paper [7].

  15. 15.

    [28]. Kolmogorov’s foundation of the minimal logic argues by means DNSs and an ad absurdum theorem stating the above conclusion. Afterwards, Kolmogorov thinks that nothing opposes to always deductively argue by means of pseudotruths from the axioms of the type A of Hilbert’s formalisation of logic. See also [10].

  16. 16.

    [1, p. 58]. The subsequent sentence (“Hence, it is necessary thus to admit that [there it is not true that do not exist] there exist simple relationships also among the volumes of [all] the gaseous substances and the number of the simple or composed molecules which compose them) constitutes the celebrated “Avogadro’s law” on the molecular constitution of whatsoever kind of matter. An analysis of the paper through its DNSs is given by [16].

  17. 17.

    Reference [20] studies a similar problem in various kinds of logic, but at the propositional level only.

  18. 18.

    Remarkably, Agkq is the same in both minimal logic and intuitionist logic. Notice that one may guess that when an author of a PO theory obtains, by arguing in minimal logic, the universal predicate Agkq, he governs by this final DNS the entire universe of his logical arguing with respect to the basic problem. At this stage, he, when meeting a false sentence, can consider it as belonging to a purely theoretical universe; hence, he can apply the intuitionist law on the false, according to which everything of this theoretical universe follows from it. In other words, when he achieves this predicate, at the same time he implicitly changes the kind of logic from the minimal one to the intuitionist one.

  19. 19.

    [19]. An analysis of the text through its DNSs is given by my paper [13].

  20. 20.

    The two requirements on the predicate on which MP is applied suggests that PRS° would have to be applied according to the same requirements, i.e. on a predicate which is decidable one and it is obtained as the result of an ad absurdum theorem. Such requirements surely would avoid all criticisms to the application of PSS°, first of all the criticism to be a metaphysical principle. In the past, a great debate aimed to clarify the use of the PSR°. From the above we conclude that PSR is not a heuristic principle for validating a mere guess on an isolated event, but an architectural principle, to be applied to an entire PO theory (see my paper [9]). Its theory-dependence explains why in the ancient times, when an analysis on PO theories was premature, it was ignored; and why in modern times, when scholars devoted little attention to both non-deductive theories and non-classical logic, it was misinterpreted.

  21. 21.

    [41, p. 27], [42, p. 274]: “… a patently non-intuitionist principle”. In fact, he applies a classical law to a specific non-classical predicate.

  22. 22.

    It is just after a chain of ad absurdum proofs (propositions nos. 17–22) that Lobachevsky stated the existence of two parallel lines, conceived as ever more prolonged segments, as an alternative hypothesis to the Euclidean one. Markov’s two requirements enlightens the implicit requirements of the common move performed by all the above authors of a PO theory, which of course concerns a method which has to rely on decidable predicates; also the common move occurring at the end of the former parts of OP theories is implicitly justified by not having reason for excluding the affirmative conclusion. Moreover, notice that the same implicit ad absurdum argument that justifies PRS° holds true for Markov’s move: “… otherwise the reality is absurd”.

  23. 23.

    Also Markov states that by means of the DNSs nos. 32, 33, 34.

References

  1. Avogadro, A.: Essay d’une manière de determiner les masses relatives des molecules élémentaires des corps…J. Phys. Chim. Hist. Nat. 73, 58–76 (1811)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Beth, E.W.: Foundations of Mathematics, ch. I, 2. Harper, New York (1959)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  3. Carnot, L.: Essai sur le machines en général, pp. 101–103. Defay, Dijon (1783)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Carnot, L.: Principes de l’équilibre et du mouvement, pp. xii–xv. Deterville, Paris (1803)

    Google Scholar 

  5. Carnot, S.: Réflexions sur la puissance motrice du feu, p. 23. Blanchard, Paris (1824)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Le Ronde d’Alembert, J.: Elémens. In: Le Ronde d’Alembert, J., Diderot, D. (eds.) Éncyclopédie Française, p. 17 (1754)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Drago, A.: Poincaré vs. Peano and Hilbert about the mathematical principle of induction. In: Greffe, J.-L., Heinzmann, G., Lorenz, K. (eds.) Henri Poincaré. Science et Philosophie, pp. 513–527. Blanchard/Springer, Paris/Berlin (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Drago, A.: Mathematics and alternative theoretical physics: the method for linking them together. Epistemologia 19, 33–50 (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Drago, A.: The birth of an alternative mechanics: Leibniz’ principle of sufficient reason. In: Poser, H., et al. (eds.) Leibniz-Kongress. Nihil Sine Ratione, vol. I, pp. 322–330. Berlin (2001)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Drago, A.: A.N. Kolmogoroff and the relevance of the double negation law in science. In: Sica, G. (ed.) Essays on the Foundations of Mathematics and Logic, pp. 57–81. Polimetrica, Milano (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Drago, A.: Four ways of logical reasoning in theoretical physics and their relationships with both the kinds of mathematics and computer science. In: Cooper, S.B., et al. (eds.) Computation and Logic in Real World, pp. 132–142. Univ. Siena Dept. of Math. Sci., Siena (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  12. Drago, A.: The square of opposition and the four fundamental choices. Logica Univers. 2, 127–141 (2008)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  13. Drago, A.: Lo scritto di Einstein sulla relatività. Esame secondo il modello di organizzazione basata su un problema. Atti Fond. G. Ronchi 64, 113–131 (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  14. Drago, A.: A logical analysis of Lobachevsky’s geometrical theory. Atti Fond. G. Ronchi 64(4), 453–481 (2010). Italian version in: Period. Mat., Ser. VIII 4, 41–52 (2004)

    Google Scholar 

  15. Drago, A.: The coincidentia oppositorum in Cusanus (1401–1464), Lanza del Vasto (1901–1981) and beyond. Epistemologia 33, 305–328 (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Drago, A., Oliva, R.: Atomism and the reasoning by non-classical logic. Hyle 5, 43–55 (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  17. Drago, A., Pisano, R.: Interpretation and reconstruction of Sadi Carnot’s Réflexions through non-classical logic. Atti Fond. G. Ronchi 59, 615–644 (2004). Italian version in: G. Fis. 41, 195–215 (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  18. Dummett, M.: Principles of Intuitionism. Clarendon, Oxford (1977)

    Google Scholar 

  19. Einstein, A.: Zur Elektrodynamik bewegter Koerper. Ann. Phys. 17, 891–921 (1905)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  20. Gabbey, D., Olivetti, N.: Goal-oriented deductions. In: Gabbey, D., Guenthner, F. (eds.) Handbook of Philosophical Logic, vol. 9, pp. 134–199. Reidel, Boston (2002)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  21. Goedel, K.: Collected Works, papers 1932 and 1933f. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1986)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  22. Grize, J.B.: Logique. In: Piaget, J. (ed.) Logique et connaissance scientifique. Éncyclopédie de la Pléiade, pp. 135–288 (206–210). Gallimard, Paris (1970)

    Google Scholar 

  23. Haak, S.: Deviant Logic. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1978)

    Google Scholar 

  24. Hand, M.: Antirealism and Falsity. In: Gabbey, D.M., Wansing, H. (eds.) What is Negation?, pp. 185–198 (188). Kluwer, Dordrecht (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  25. Heyting, A.: Intuitionism. An Introduction, Sect. 2. North-Holland, Amsterdam (1971)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  26. Kleene, C.: Introduction to Metamathematics, pp. 318–319. Van Nostrand, Princeton (1952)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  27. Klein, M.J.: Thermodynamics in Einstein’s thought. Science 57, 505–516 (1967)

    Google Scholar 

  28. Kolmogorov, A.N.: On the principle ‘tertium non datur’. Mat. Sb. 32, 646–667 (1924/1925). Engl. translation in: van Heijenoorth, J. (ed.) From Frege to Goedel, pp. 416–437. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1967)

    Google Scholar 

  29. Leibniz, G.W.: Letter to Arnauld, 14-7-1686, Gerh. II, Q., Opusc. 402, 513

    Google Scholar 

  30. Lobachevsky, N.I.: Geometrische Untersuchungen zur der Theorien der Parallellineen. Finkl, Berlin (1840). Engl. translation as an Appendix to: Bonola, R.: Non-Euclidean Geometry. Dover, New York (1955)

    Google Scholar 

  31. Markov, A.A.: On constructive mathematics. Tr. Mat. Inst. Steklova 67, 8–14 (1962). Also in: Am. Math. Soc. Transl. 98(2), 1–9 (1971)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  32. Miller, A.I.: Albert Einstein’s Special Theory of Relativity, pp. 123–142. Addison-Wesley, Reading (1981)

    Google Scholar 

  33. Parsons, T.: Things that are right wit the traditional square of opposition. Logica Univers. 2, 3–11 (2008)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  34. Poincaré, H.: La Science et l’Hypothèse, Ch. “Optique et Electricité”. Hermann, Paris (1903)

    Google Scholar 

  35. Poincaré, H.: La Valeur de la Science, Ch. VII. Flammarion, Paris (1905)

    Google Scholar 

  36. Poincaré, H.: Science et Méthode, p. 187. Flammarion, Paris (1912)

    Google Scholar 

  37. Prawitz, D.: Meaning and proof. The conflict between classical and intuitionist logic. Theoria 43, 6–39 (1976)

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  38. Prawitz, D., Melmnaas, P.-E.: A survey of some connections between classical intuitionistic and minimal logic. In: Schmidt, A., Schuette, H. (eds.) Contributions to Mathematical Logic, pp. 215–229. North-Holland, Amsterdam (1968)

    Google Scholar 

  39. Tennant, N.: Natural Logic, p. 57. Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh

    Google Scholar 

  40. Troesltra, A.: Remarks on intuitionism and the philosophy of mathematics. In: Costantini, D., Galavotti, M.C. (eds.) Nuovi Problemi della Logica e della Filosofia della Scienza, pp. 211–228 (223). CLUEB, Bologna (1991)

    Google Scholar 

  41. Troelstra, A., van Dalen, D.: Constructivism in Mathematics, vol. 1. North-Holland, Amsterdam (1988)

    Google Scholar 

  42. van Dalen, D.: Intuitionist logic. In: Gabbey, D.M., Guenthner, F. (eds.) Handbook of Mathematical Logic, vol. II, pp. 225–449 (226 and 230). Reidel, Dordrecht (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  43. Woods, J., Irvine, A.: Aristotle’s early logic. In: Gabbey, D.M., Woods, J. (eds) Handbook of History of Logic, vol. 1, pp. 27–99 (66). Elsevier, New York (2004)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I acknowledge two anonymous referees for an improvement of my previous logical framework, and David Braithwhaite for the correction on my English text.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Antonino Drago .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix: The analysis through the double negations of [31]

Appendix: The analysis through the double negations of [31]

Notice that modal words are equivalent, via S4 translation, to DNSs; these words are wave underlined.

  1. (1)

    Recently the constructive trend in mathematics has been significantly developed. Its goal is to base all investigations on constructive objects and to carry them out within the bounds of the abstraction of potential realizability and without use of the abstraction of actual (= not potential) infinity; …

  2. (2)

    … it rejects the so-called pure existence [= not constructive] theorems, …

  3. (3)

    … since the existence of an object with given properties is considered proved only when a realizable method for the construction of an object with those properties bas been indicated … .

  4. (4)

    … We do not define the concept of a constructive object, but rather clarify it.

  5. (5)

    In constructive mathematical theories we limit ourselves to the consideration of constructive objects of some standard type, which frees us from the necessity of formulating a general definition of a constructive object.

  6. (6)

    The abstraction of identity is used here in a natural way; we identify the words (1) and (2); we abstract away from their having any differences; we say that they are the same word … .

  7. (7)

    … When considering words in a given alphabet we are forced into an abstraction of another kind—into the abstraction of potential existence … .

  8. (8)

    … It consists in abstracting away from the practical limits of our possibilities in space, time and material when it comes to the existence of words … .

  9. (9)

    … We cannot write on a given blackboard of a given dimension words of arbitrary [= unlimited] length … .

  10. (10)

    … We abstract away from this practical impossibility and begin to argue as if this were possible.

  11. (11)

    This does not at all mean that we begin to consider the “sequence of naturals” as an infinite “object.” …

  12. (12)

    … Such a consideration would involve an abstraction of an actual infinity, …

  13. (13)

    … taking us beyond the limits of constructive mathematics and into something characteristic of the so-called “classical” mathematics.

  14. (14)

    In “classical” mathematics there have been many “pure existence theorems,” which consist in assertions about the “existence” of objects with certain properties even despites a complete ignorance of means to construct such an object.

  15. (15)

    Constructive mathematics rejects such propositions [on pure existence] …

  16. (16)

    … In constructive mathematics the existence of an object with certain properties is considered proved when a potentially realizable method has been given for the construction of an object with the given properties.

  17. (17)

    This understanding of disjunction does not permit one to take as true the law of the excluded middle: “P or not P.”…

  18. (18)

    …2. The formulation and development of the constructive trend took place on the basis of work that appeared in the 1930s which made precise the concept of an algorithm, freeing this concept from vagueness and subjectivity… .

  19. (19)

    As we know, this vague concept of a was made precise in the 30s in the work of several men, who took different approaches: Church, Kleene, Turing, Post. The theories constructed by these men—Kleene’s theory of recursive functions, Church’s calculus of λ-conversion, the theory of Turing machines and Post’s theory of finite combinatory processes—turned out to be to one another and to lead to essentially the same formulation of the concept of an algorithm …

  20. (20)

    … New formulations of this concept, also to the previous ones, were constructed one after another by other authors, …

  21. (21)

    … and even in the present time new theories of algorithms are continually being published that are to the previous theories … .

  22. (22)

    … It is not for us at this time to look into these theories to try to find the best one.

  23. (23)

    The algorithm also determines the end of the procedure which occur.

  24. (24)

    The theory of normal algorithms is constructed which in the framework of abstract existence … .

  25. (25)

    … The words in the alphabet A under consideration and the schemes of the normal algorithms in A are realizable constructive objects … .

  26. (26)

    … The procedure itself of applying a normal algorithm to a given word is considered by us to be a realizable procedure.

  27. (27)

    I consider it [is] to apply here an argument “by contradiction”,

  28. (28)

    … i.e. to assert that the algorithm A is applicable to the word P if the assumption that the process of applying A to P continues indefinitely leads to a contradiction.

  29. (29)

    If I defend this means of argument here, it is not because I find it without error according to my intuition, …

  30. (30)

    … but rather, firstly, because I see no reasonable reason for rejecting it, …

  31. (31)

    … and secondly, because arguments of this type make it to construct a constructive mathematics that is well able to serve contemporary natural Science … .

  32. (32)

    … I insist that this does not go beyond the bounds of the constructive direction: …

  33. (33)

    … the abstraction of actual infinity is not made, …

  34. (34)

    … existence continues to coincide with a realizable construction …

  35. (35)

    … If we assert on the basis of the proved impossibility of the indefinite continuation of a given procedure that this procedure ends, then this yields a perfectly well-defined method of construction: continue the process until its completion … .

  36. (36)

    … The circumstance that the number of steps cannot be bounded “in advance”, here changes nothing of importance … .

  37. (37)

    … It is even that the requirement that this number be bounded in advance will ever be formulated precisely and objectively … .

  38. (38)

    … It is not difficult to see that this method for proving the applicability of an algorithm …

  39. (39)

    one to justify the following method of argument … .

  40. (40)

    Let P a property, ad let there be an algorithm that decide for every natural number n whether or not n has the property P. If the proposition that no number has the property P leads to a contradiction there is a natural number with the property P.

The analysis of this list of DNS is easy. The list presents one only ad absurdum proof; it is exposed wordily by the DNSs 29 and 30. Hence, there is one unit of arguing only. The following DNSs are aimed to illustrate the result obtained. After the DNS 40 the development of the theory assumes the last DNS as a new hypothesis.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Basel

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Drago, A. (2012). Pluralism in Logic: The Square of Opposition, Leibniz’ Principle of Sufficient Reason and Markov’s Principle. In: Béziau, JY., Jacquette, D. (eds) Around and Beyond the Square of Opposition. Studies in Universal Logic. Springer, Basel. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-0348-0379-3_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics