Skip to main content
Log in

Some Remarks on “Language-Created Entities”

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Some entities, such as fictional characters, propositions, properties, events and numbers are prima facie promising candidates for owing their existence to our linguistic and conceptual practices. However, it is notoriously hard to pin down just what sets such allegedly “language-created” entities apart from ordinary entities. The present paper considers some of the features that are supposed to distinguish between entities of the two kinds and argues that, on an independently plausible account of what it takes to individuate objects, the criteria let in more than friends of the strategy might be happy with.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For instance, Amie Thomasson has identified various different ways in which the strategy allows us to see entities as language-created (Thomasson 2001). Thomas Hofweber has argued that the characteristic uses of referring expressions that Schiffer and others take to be responsible for the “creation” of entities serve a different communicative function so that the strategy fails (Hofweber 2007). Luca Moretti defends Schiffer’s strategy and provides a general account of the features of the entities constructed by linguistic practices (Moretti 2008).

  2. Moretti briefly discusses this question (Moretti 2008) but, to my mind, ends up being too optimistic on behalf of the constructivist.

  3. Crawford Elder has recently criticized this strategy of rendering linguistic constructivism compatible with the platitude that if properties exist at all, they existed before humans started engaging in any linguistic practices and they would have existed even if no language-using creatures ever had (Elder 2006). Elsewhere, I have developed an account that allows the linguistic constructivist to resist Elder’s criticism (Einheuser 2006).

  4. Schiffer is quoting from Johnston (1988).

  5. See Hofweber (2007) and Moretti (2008) for detailed discussion of such inferences and their role in generating language-created entities.

  6. A sortal concept, expressed by a sortal term, is a concept that conveys both criteria of application and criteria of identity governing the objects that fall under it. The Stanford Encyclopedia entry on sortals (Grandy 2007) provides an informative overview.

  7. See Jonathan Lowe’s recent defense of this view against a series of objections in his Lowe (2007).

  8. Again, see Lowe (2007) for a defense of this sort of claim.

  9. Amie Thomasson, in Thomasson (2007), has made a convincing case for why we need to conceive of our terms as associated with sortal concepts, though she talks of criteria of application and co-application rather than of sortals.

  10. Amie Thomasson makes a similar point when she says that such entities are “relatively minimal” (Thomasson 2001). She argues that the inferences in question are analytic, but she combines this view with a robust realism about the material objects referred to Thomasson (2007).

References

  • Einheuser, I. (2006). Counterconventional conditionals. Philosophical Studies, 127(3), 459–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elder, C. L. (2006). Conventionalism and realism-imitating counterfactuals. Philosophical Quarterly, 56, 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grandy, R. (2007). Sortals. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Available at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sortals/. Cited 2 May 2009.

  • Hofweber, T. (2007). Innocent statements and their metaphysically loaded counterparts. Philosophers’ Imprint, 1, 1–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (1988). The end of the theory of meaning. Mind and Language, 3(1), 28–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1972). Naming and necessity. In D. Davidson & G. Harman (Eds.), Semantics of natural language (pp. 253–355). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. (2007). Sortals and the individuation of objects. Mind and Language, 22(5), 514–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moretti, L. (2008). The ontological status of minimal entities. Philosophical Studies, 141, 97–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. (1996). Language-created, language-independent entities. Philosophical Topics, 24(1), 149–167.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. (2003). The things we mean. Oxford University Press.

  • Thomasson, A. (2001). Ontological minimalism. American Philosophical Quarterly, 38, 319–331.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. (2007). Ordinary objects. Oxford University Press.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Iris Einheuser.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Einheuser, I. Some Remarks on “Language-Created Entities”. Acta Anal 24, 185–192 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-009-0052-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-009-0052-6

Keywords

Navigation