Skip to main content

Unity of Science and Pluralism: Cognitive Neurosciences of Racial Prejudice as a Case Study

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Special Sciences and the Unity of Science

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 24))

Abstract

A consideration of the recent history of philosophy reveals that when thinking about unity of science, philosophers have mainly been thinking of unity through reduction of higher level theories to lower level theories. In other words, if unity was to be achieved it was through intertheoretic reduction. Lately, though, some philosophers (Darden and Maull, Philos Sci 44:43–64, 1977; McCauley and Bechtel, Theory Psychol 11:736–760, 2001; Mitchell and Dietrich, Am Nat 168:S73–S79, 2006) have started to question this exclusive focus on intertheoretic reduction in the discussions concerning the unity of science. These philosophers have also come to reject the global project of unification for more modest and local forms of unification: This is the area of pluralism. Pluralism complicates tremendously our understanding of the relations between theories. In fact, pluralism suggests that we are facing two distinct tasks: (1) Developing a typology of the intertheoretic relations; (2) Understanding on a case-by-case basis the relation between specific theories or specific frameworks. I believe that progress has been made with respect to (1), but I want to improve on the current understanding of the typology of intertheoretic relations. I take (2) to be essential: Many scientists have failed to understand what pluralism entails. They view their theories to be simply inconsistent with each other (when sometimes, they are not). It is important to understand the relations between actual sciences and between actual theories in order to avoid futile arguments and to develop better theories. In this paper, I will present Sandra Mitchell’s typology of inter-theoretic relations. I will then focus on a case study—the relations between the neurosciences and social cognitive psychology of racial prejudice. What will emerge is that the pluralism proposed by Mitchell should be enriched further to understand the real nature of the unity proposed in certain fields of science.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    “Since Nagel’s influential model of reduction by derivation, most discussions of unity of science have been cast in terms of reductions between concepts and between theories” (Cat 1998, p. 532; see also Sarkar 1992, p. 168 for a similar view).

  2. 2.

    For some clarification on the notion of level, see Sect. 11.2.

  3. 3.

    Similarly, Mitchell et al. (1997), concludes that the Nagelian project “has failed” (p. 108). Actual causes and time of death will not be discussed here.

  4. 4.

    For example, Neurath wrote the following: “The development of physicalist sociology does not mean the transfer of laws of physics to living things and their groups … Comprehensive sociological laws can be found, …, without the need to go back to the microstructure, and thereby to build up these sociological laws from physical ones” (quoted by Cat et al. 1996, p. 347).

  5. 5.

    His stance is “new wave” because its attempt to capture some important aspects of the practice internal to science while downplaying the importance of general external philosophical questions can be seen as a reincarnation of the carnapian distinction between ‘internal’ and ‘external’ questions (on this, see section 5.2 of Chap.1 of his 2003).

  6. 6.

    “There is no need to evoke psychological causal explanations, and in fact scientists stop evoking and developing them, once real neurolobiological explanations are on offer” (Bickle 2003, p. 110).

  7. 7.

    As he puts it: “ … the new wave approach construes the relation as the construction of an image … of the set-theoretic structure of models of the reduced theory T R within the set comprising reducing theory T B . ” (2003, p. 27)

  8. 8.

    Bechtel and Hamilton (2007) and Faucher (2006) have insisted that while mechanism is typically reductionnist in spirit, it does not have to maintain that a complete causal story can be told at the lower level. Explanations of many phenomena will typically need to make reference to causal interactions of the mechanism with the environment (which will change the conditions of the parts and their mode of operation).

  9. 9.

    Which is not to say that it will not sometimes be an accurate description, see for instance Bickle’s remarks about the molecular neurosciences of social recognition memory (2006, p. 423).

  10. 10.

    Critics of Mitchell’s position have characterize here position, on the basis of her use of examples of the kind mentioned, a form of “modest pluralism” for her view about the disunity of science “seems to reduce to … monism because it is consistent with the idea that for every particular phenomenon, there is a single, best account” (Kellert et al. 2006, p. xii). More “radical” forms of pluralism are possible in which explanations are not expected to resolve into monism. See for instance, Fehr (2006) on explanations of the evolution of sex and Longino (2006) on the study of human behavior.

  11. 11.

    Longino is quite clear that this form of compatible pluralism does not lead to integration: “If their partiality is accepted, each approach can be seen to produce some knowledge of behavior by answering the questions distinctive of it with methods that are also distinctive. But none of the approaches can yield a complete account … Each approach can produce partial knowledge. In concert, they constitute a nonunifiable plurality of partial knowledges” (2006, p. 127; my emphasis).

  12. 12.

    To be more precise, in this case, one should note that the conflict was between theories instantiating different approaches. I will talk about a conflict of approaches or traditions of research to make short.

  13. 13.

    For instance, Matthew Lieberman wrote that “although the social sciences and neurosciences have been hugely successful enterprises in their own right, there is a sense that we can now build an intellectual superhighway between themthat will allow us to catalyze the insights from both into a new kind of science that will yield important insights into the basic nature of the human mind…” (2006, p. 1; my emphasis).

  14. 14.

    Cacioppo and Bernston defined social psychology as “the scientific study of social behavior, with an emphasis on understanding the individual in a social context. Accordingly, social psychologists study a diverse range of topics ranging from intrapersonal processes shaped by or in response to others, such as the self, attitudes, emotions, social identity, normative beliefs, social perception, social cognition, and interpersonal attraction; to interpersonal processes such as persuasion and social influence, verbal and nonverbal communication, interpersonal relationships, altruism, and aggression, to group processes such as social facilitation, cooperation and competition; …” (2006, p. 91). In the late 1970’s, social cognitive psychology emerged as a subfield of social psychology, focusing on information-processing accounts of the phenomena to be explained. With the growing success of cognitive neuroscience (Gazzaniga 1995), it was a matter of time before a discipline (or a sub-discipline) like “social cognitive neuroscience” would emerge.

  15. 15.

    As Cunningham et al. put it: “[I]mplicit prejudice can … be defined as the automatic cognitive association between a social group and negative evaluation” (2004, p. 1334).

  16. 16.

    As Darden and Maull put it: “… an interfield theory is likely to be generated when background knowledge indicates that relations already exist between the fields, when the fields share an interest in explaining different aspects of the same phenomenon, and when questions arise about that phenomenon within a field which cannot be answered with the techniques and concepts of that field” (1978, p. 50).

  17. 17.

    As Susan Fiske puts it: “People accentuate differences between categories and minimize differences within categories (Capozza and Nanni 1986; Tajfel 1970; Taylor 1981). People tag other people by race, gender, and age, so they confuse people within groups and differentiate them between groups (Arcuri 1982; Taylor et al. 1978).” (2000, p. 304)

  18. 18.

    The same process of construction of a “heuristic model” is standard in other domain of social cognitive neuroscience (and in cognitive neuroscience). As Ochsner and Lieberman (2001) put it: “When relatively little is known about the neural systems involved in a given form of behavior or cognition, initial studies serve more to identify brain correlates for those phenomena than to test theories about how and why the phenomena occur. This has been the case for many areas of cognitive neuroscience research as well. Ultimately, it will be important to move beyond brain-behavior correlations, but that can only happen when researchers in the fields have built a baseline of knowledge about the brain systems underlying specific types of social or emotional processing … Once one has an idea of which processes a brain area carries out, one can make use of that knowledge to test hypotheses about the involvement of those processes in a given behavior” (p.725 and 729; my emphasis).

  19. 19.

    Neuroscientists seems to acknowledged the priority of social psychology. For instance, Todorov and his colleagues write: “Brain imaging and event-related potential (ERP) studies on race perception have relied on the rich literature in social psychology as a watershed for exploring the neural dynamics involved in stereotyping, prejudice, and other forms of outgroup perception” (Todorov et al. 2006, p. 78).

  20. 20.

    Thus, we disagree with Phelps and Thomas above: The integration of neuroscience and social psychology has led to the discovery of new psychological phenomena.

  21. 21.

    See Öhman et Mineka (2003) for a discussion of “prepared learning” for fear-relevant stimuli.

  22. 22.

    The model is also as good as the neurological theories it is build on. For instance, it might be tempting to interpret amygdala activation in seeing other faces as suggesting that fear is a component of stereotyping. But one might want to resist this temptation by considering that amygdala activation has been associated not only with fear or negative evaluation, but also with positive emotions such as amusement and perception and happiness (Willingham and Dunn 2003, p. 666).

  23. 23.

    Grantham talks of “unity” but following my earlier remark, I will rather speak in term of integration.

  24. 24.

    Some might say that this is because the theories in each domains are not ripe for reduction or that the theories of cognitive social psychology are false (and therefore could not be derived or reduce to true theories). But one could argue the other way around and say that neurosciences of memory are reductionist because they are not ripe. Bechtel and Abrahamsen (2008) have advocated such a view showing that reduction, in certain case, is a first step that is then to be complemented by an account that considers the processes that were left behind in the reductionistic quest. My position is that in the case I studied, it is very unlikely that we will be able to do away with the cognitive and social levels of explanation.

References

  • Allport, G. 1954. The nature of prejudice. Reading: Addison-Wesley Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Amodio, D.M., and P.G. Devine. 2006. Stereotyping and evaluation in implicit race bias: Evidence for independent constructs and unique effects on behavior. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology91(4): 652–661.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banaji, M.R. 2002. Stereotypes, social psychology of. In International encyclopedia of the social and behavioral sciences, ed. N. Smelser and P. Baltes, 15100–15104. New York: Pergamon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beatty, J. 1994. Ernst Mayr and proximate/ultimate distinction. Biology and Philosophy9: 333–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. 2004. The epistemology of evidence in cognitive neuroscience. In Philosophy and the life sciences: A reader, ed. R. Skipper, C. Allen, R.A. Ankeny, C.F. Craver, L. Darden, G.Mikkelson, and R. Richardson. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., and A. Hamilton. 2007. Reductionism, integration, and the unity of the sciences. In Philosophy of science: Focal issues, The handbook of the philosophy of science, vol. 1, ed. T.Kuipers. New York: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. 1998. Psychoneural reduction: The New wave. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. 2003. Philosophy and neuroscience: A ruthlessly reductive account. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. 2006. Reducing mind to molecular pathways: Explicating the reductionism implicit in current mainstream neuroscience. Synthese151(3): 411–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cacioppo, J.T., and G. Bernston. 2006. A bridge linking social psychology and the neurosciences. In Bridging social psychology: Benefits of transdisciplinary approaches, ed. P.A.M. Van Lange, 91–96. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cacioppo, J.T., P.S. Visser, and C.L. Pickett (eds.). 2006. Social neuroscience: People thinking about thinking people. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cat, J. 2007. Scientific Unity. In Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/scientific-unity/.

  • Cat, J., H. Chang, and N. Cartwright. 1996. Otto Neurath: Politics and the unity of science. In The disunity of science: Boundaries, contexts, and power, ed. P. Galison and D.J. Stump, 347–369. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. 1965. Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. 1986. Neurophilosophy: Toward a unified science of the mind-brain. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cosmides, L., J. Tooby, and R. Kurzban. 2003. Perceptions of race. Trends in Cognitive Sciences7(4): 173–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C.F., and L. Darden. 2001. Discovering mechanisms in neurobiology: The case of spatial memory. In Theory and method in neuroscience, ed. P.K. Machamer, R. Grush, and P.McLaughlin, 112–137. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Creath, R. 1996. The unity of science: Carnap, Neurath and beyond. In The disunity of science: Boundaries, contexts, and power, ed. P. Galison and D.J. Stump, 158–169. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cunningham, W.A., J.B. Nezlek, and M. Banaji. 2004. Implicit and explicit ethnocentrism: Revisiting ideologies of prejudice. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin30(10): 1332–1346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L., and N. Maull. 1977. Interfield theories. Philosophy of Science44: 43–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Decety, J. 2007. A social cognitive neuroscience model of human empathy. In Social neuroscience: Integrating biological and psychological explanations of social behavior, ed. E. Harmon-Jones and P. Winkielman, 246–270. New York: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. 1993. The disorder of things: Metaphysical foundations of the disunity of science. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. 1996. Metaphysical disorder and scientific disunity. In The disunity of science: Boundaries, contexts, and power, ed. P. Galison and D.J. Stump, 101–117. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eberhardt, J.L. 2005. Imaging race. American Psychologist60(2): 181–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Faucher, L. 2006. What’s behind a smile: Commentary on Schaffner. Synthese151(3): 403–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, C. 2006. Explanations of the evolution of sex: A plurality of local mechanisms. In Scientific pluralism, Minnesota studies in philosophy of science, vol. XIX, ed. S.H. Kellert, H.E. Longino, and C.K. Waters, 167–189. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiske, S. 2000. Stereotyping, prejudice, and discrimination at the seam between the centuries: Evolution, culture, mind, and brain. European Journal of Social Psychology 30: 299–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fiske, S. 2002. What we know now about bias and intergroup conflict, the problem of the century. Current Directions in Psychological Science11(4): 123–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J.A. 1974. Special sciences (or: The disunity of science as a working hypothesis). Synthese28: 97–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J.A. Look. Review of consilience: The unity of knowledge. In The London Review of Books, ed. E. O. Wilson, 1988. 29 Oct (online: http://www.lrb.co.uk/v20/n21/fodo01_.html).

  • Frith, C., and U. Frith. 2007. Social cognition in humans. Current Biology17(16): R724–R732.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, I., P. Skudlarski, J.C. Gore, and A.W. Anderson. 2000. Expertise for cars and birds recruits brain areas involved in face recognition. Nature Neuroscience3(2): 191–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gazzaniga, M.S. (ed.). 1995. The cognitive neurosciences. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. 2002. Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science69: S342–S353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Golby, A.J., J.D.E. Gabrieli, J.Y. Chiao, and J.L. Eberhardt. 2001. Differential responses in the fusiform region to same-race and other-race faces. Nature Neuroscience4(8): 845–850.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grantham, T. 2004. Conceptualizing the (dis)unity of science. Philosophy of Science, vol.71: 133–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gray Hardcastle, V. 1992. Reduction, explanatory extension, and the mind-brain sciences. Philosophy of Science59: 408–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green, J.D., R.B. Sommerville, L.E. Nystrom, J.M. Darley, and J.D. Cohen. 2001. An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science293: 2105–2108. Sept. 14th.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P.E. 2004. Instinct in the '50s: The British reception of Konrad Lorenz's theory of instinctive behaviour. Biology and Philosophy19(4): 609–631.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. 1996. The disunities of science. In The disunity of science: Boundaries, contexts, and power, ed. P. Galison and D. Stump, 38–74. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, L.T., and S.T. Fiske. 2006. Dehumanizing the lowest of the low: Neuro-imaging responses to extreme outgroups. Psychological Science17: 847–853.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haslam, N., B. Bastian, P. Bain, and Y. Kshima. 2006. Psychological essentialism, implicit theories, and intergroup relations. Group Processes & Intergroup Relations9(1): 63–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ito, T.A., G.R. Urland, E. Willadsen-Jensen, and J. Correll. 2006. The social neuroscience of stereotyping and prejudice: Using event-related potentials to study social perception. In Social neuroscience: People thinking about thinking people, ed. J.T. Cacioppo, P.S. Visser, and C.L. Pickett, 189–208. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, M. 2002. Social psychology of prejudice. Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kanwisher, N. 2000. Domain specificity in face perception. Nature Neuroscience3(8): 759–763.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kellert, S.H., H.E. Longino, and C.K. Waters. 2006. The pluralist stance. In Scientific pluralism, Minnesota studies in philosophy of science, vol. XIX, ed. S.H. Kellert, H.E. Longino, and C.K. Waters, vii–xxix. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, D., and E. Roedder. 2008. Racial cognition and ethics of implicit bias. Philosophical Compass3(3): 522–540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. 1998. Mind in a physical world: An essay on the mind-body problem and mental causation. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. 1984. 1953 and all that: A tale of two sciences. The Philosophical Review93: 335–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. 1999. Unification as a regulative ideal. Perspectives on Science7(3): 337–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S.M. 1980. Image and mind. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. 1962. The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kurzban, R., and S. Neuberg. 2005. Managing ingroup and outgroup relationships. In Handbook of evolutionary psychology, ed. D. Buss, 653–675. Hoboken: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ledoux, J. 1996. The emotional brain. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin, S. ms. Social psychological evidence on race and racism.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lieberman, M. 2006.Social cognitive and affective neuroscience: When opposites attract. Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience1(1–2): 1–2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lieberman, ms. Social cognitive neuroscience.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H.E. 2006. Theoretical pluralism and the scientific study of behavior. In Scientific pluralism, Minnesota studies in philosophy of science, vol. XIX, ed. S.H. Kellert, H.E. Longino, and C.K. Waters, 102–131. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Looren de Jong, H. 2006. Explicating pluralism: Where the mind to molecule gets off the track—reply to Bickle. Synthese151: 435–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., L. Darden, and C. Craver. 2000. Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science67: 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., and L. Faucher. 2005a. Why do we think racially? A critical journey into culture and evolution. In Handbook of categorizatin in cognitive science, ed. C. Lefèbvre and H. Cohen, 1009–1033. New York: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., and L. Faucher. 2005b. Social construction and the concept of race. Philosophy of Science72: 1208–1219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCauley, R. 1996. Explanatory pluralism and the coevolution of theories in science. In The churchlands and their critics, ed. R. McCauley. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCauley, R.N., and W. Bechtel. 2001. Explanatory pluralism and the Heuristic Identity theory. Theory and Psychology11: 736–760.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S.D. 2002. Integrative pluralism. Biology and Philosophy17: 55–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S.D. 2003. Biological complexity and integrative pluralism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S.D., and M.R. Dietrich. 2006. Integration without unification: An argument for pluralism in the biological sciences. The American Naturalist168: S73–S79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S.D., L. Daston, G. Gigerenzer, N. Sesardic, and P.B. Sloep. 1997. The why and hows of interdisciplinarity. In Human by nature: Between biology and the social sciences, ed. P.Weingart, S.D. Mitchell, P. Richerson, and S. Maasen, 103–150. Mahwah: Erlbaum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. 1961. The structure of science. New York: Hartcourt, Brace and World.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ochsner, K.N., and M. Lieberman. 2001. The emergence of social cognitive neuroscience. American Psychologist56: 77–734.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Öhman, A., and S. Mineka. 2003. The malicious serpent: Snakes as a prototypical stimulus for an evolved module of fear. Current Directions in Psychological Science12(1): 5–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olsson, A., and E.A. Phelps. 2007. Social learning of fear. Nature Neuroscience10(9): 1095–1102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olsson, A., J. Ebert, M. Banaji, and E.A. Phelps. 2005. The role of social groups in the persistence of learned fear. Science308: 785–797.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oppenheim, P., H. Putnam, et al. 1958. The unity of science as a working hypothesis. In Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, vol. 2, ed. H. Feigl. Minneapolis: Minnesota University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phelps, E.A. 2001. Faces and races in the brain. Nature Neuroscience4(8): 775–776.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phelps, E.A., and L.A. Thomas. 2003. Race, behavior and the brain: The role of neuroimaging in social behaviors. Political Psychology24(4): 747–758.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pratto, F., J. Sidanius, J., and S. Levin. 2006. Social dominance theory and the dynamics of intergroup relations: Taking stock and looking forward. In W. Stroebe, and M. Hewstone (eds.), European Review of Social Psychology 17: 271–320.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z.W. 1981. The imagery debate: Analogue media versus tacit knowledge. Psychological Review88: 16–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Queller, D.C., and J.E. Strassmann. 1998. Kin selection and social insects. Bioscience48: 165–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, A.W. 2006. The many unities of science: Politics, semantics, and ontology. In Scientific pluralism, Minnesota studies in philosophy of science, vol. XIX, ed. S.H. Kellert, H.E. Longino, and C.K. Waters, 1–25. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, S. 1992. Models of reduction and categories of reductionism. Synthese91: 167–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seymour, B., T. Singer, and R. Dolan. 2007. The neurobiology of punishment. Nature Reviews Neuroscience8: 300–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tajfel, J., and J.C. Turner. 1986. The social identity theory of inter-group behavior. In Psychology of intergroup relations, ed. S. Worchel and L.W. Austin, 2–24. Chicago: Nelson-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tinbergen, N. 1963. On aims and methods in ethology. Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie20: 410–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Todorov, A., L.T. Harris, and S. Fiske. 2006. Toward socially inspired social neuroscience. Brain Research1079: 76–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M.E., and S. Fiske. 2005. Controlling racial prejudice: Social-cognitive goals affect amygdala and stereotype activation. Psychological Science16(1): 56–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Willingham, D.T., and E.W. Dunn. 2003. What neuroimaging and brain localization can do, cannot do, and should not do for social psychology. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology84(4): 662–671.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. 1976. Reductionism, levels of organization, and the mind-body problem. In Consciousness and the brain: A scientific and philosophical inquiry, ed. I. Savodnik, 202–267. New York: Plenum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. 1994. The ontology of complex systems: Levels, perspectives, and causal thickets. Canadian Journal of Philosophy. Supplemental Volume20: 207–274.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wylie, A. 1999. Rethinking unity as a ‘working hypothesis’ for philosophy of science: How archeologists exploit the disunities of science. Perspectives on Science7(3): 293–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wylie, A. 2000. Questions of evidence, legitimacy, and the (dis)unity of science. American Antiquity65(2): 227–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Many thanks to Edouard Machery who read and commented several versions of this paper. He is responsible of many of the good ideas in it. Thank you also to Frédéric Bouchard and Pierre Poirier for comments on the last version of the paper. I tried my best to accommodate all their comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Luc Faucher .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Faucher, L. (2012). Unity of Science and Pluralism: Cognitive Neurosciences of Racial Prejudice as a Case Study. In: Pombo, O., Torres, J., Symons, J., Rahman, S. (eds) Special Sciences and the Unity of Science. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 24. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-2030-5_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics