skip to main content
article

Thinking and Computing: Computers as Special Kinds of Signs

Published:01 June 1997Publication History
Skip Abstract Section

Abstract

Cognitive science has been dominated by the computational conception that cognition is computation across representations. To the extent to which cognition as computation across representations is supposed to be a purposive, meaningful, algorithmic, problem-solving activity, however, computers appear to be incapable of cognition. They are devices that can facilitate computations on the basis of semantic grounding relations as special kinds of signs. Even their algorithmic, problem-solving character arises from their interpretation by human users. Strictly speaking, computers as such – apart from human users – are not only incapable of cognition, but even incapable of computation, properly construed. If we want to understand the nature of thought, then we have to study thinking, not computing, because they are not the same thing.

References

  1. Church, A. (1959), 'Logistic System', in D. Runes, ed., Dictionary of Philosophy, Ames, IO: Little-field, Adams & Company, pp. 182-183.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  2. Cleland, C. (1993), 'Is the Church-Turing Thesis True?', Minds and Machines 3, pp. 283-312.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  3. Cleland, C. (1995), 'Effective Procedures and Computable Functions', Minds and Machines 5, pp. 9-23.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  4. Coates, P. (1997), 'Meaning, Mistake and Miscalculation', Minds and Machines 7, pp. 171-197. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  5. Cohen, D. (1986), Introduction to Computer Theory. New York, NY: John Wiley & Sons. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  6. Dennett, D. (1971), 'Intentional Systems', Journal of Philosophy 68, pp. 87-106; reprinted in Hauge-land (1981), pp. 220-242. Page references are to the reprinted version.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  7. Dennett, D. (1981), 'Three Kinds of Intentional Psychology', in R. A. Healey, ed., Reduction, Time and Reality, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 37-61.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  8. Dennett, D. (1991), Consciousness Explained. Boston, MA: Little, Brown & Co.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  9. Dennett, D. (1995), Darwin's Dangerous Idea. New York, NY: Simon & Schuster.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  10. Dennett, D. (1996), Kinds of Minds. New York, NY: Basic Books.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  11. Fetzer, J. H. (1981), Scientific Knowledge. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel Publishing Company.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  12. Fetzer, J. H. (1988), 'Signs and Minds: An Introduction to the Theory of Semiotic Systems', in J. Fetzer, ed., Aspects of Artificial Intelligence, Dordrecht, The Netherlands, pp. 13-161.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  13. Fetzer, J. H. (1989), 'Language and Mentality: Computational, Representational, and Dispositional Conceptions', Behaviorism 17, pp. 21-39.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  14. Fetzer, J. H. (1990a), Artificial Intelligence: Its Scope and Limits. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  15. Fetzer, J.H. (1990b), "Artificial Intelligence Meets David Hume: A Reply to Pat Hayes", International Journal of Expert Systems 3, pp. 239-247. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  16. Fetzer, J. H. (1991), Philosophy and Cognitive Science. New York, NY: Paragon House Publishers.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  17. Fetzer, J. H. (1993a), "A Piece of My Mind: Lundberg, JFK and JAMA", The Fourth Decade 9, pp. 35-40.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  18. Fetzer, J. H. (1993b), 'Review of Merlin Donald's Origins of the Modern Mind', Philosophical Psychology 6, pp. 339-341.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  19. Fetzer, J. H. (1993c), "Primitive Concepts: Habits, Conventions, and Laws", in J. Fetzer, ed., Definitions and Definability, Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 51-68.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  20. Fetzer, J. H. (1994a), 'Mental Algorithms: Are Minds Computational Systems?', Pragmatics and Cognition 2, pp. 1-29.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  21. Fetzer, J. H. (1994b), 'Review of Donald Griffin's Animal Mind', Human Ethology Newsletter 9, pp. 15-17.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  22. Fetzer, J. H. (1996a), 'Do Animals have Minds?, Discussion Review: M. S. Dawkins, Through Our Eyes Only: The Search for Animal Consciousness', The Journal of Social and Evolutionary Systems 19, pp. 187-192.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  23. Fetzer, J. H. (1996b), Philosophy and Cognitive Science, 2nd edition. New York, NY: Paragon House Publishers.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  24. Fetzer, J. H. (1997), 'Review of Daniel Dennett's Kinds of Minds', Philosophical Psychology 10, pp. 113-115.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  25. Fetzer, J. H. (forthcoming), "People are Not Computers: (Most) Thought Processes are Not Computational Procedures", Journal of Experimental and Theoretical AI.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  26. Hartshorne, P. and P. Weiss (1960), The Collected Papers of Charles S. Peirce. Vols. 1 and 2. Cambridge, M A: Harvard University Press.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  27. Haugeland, J., ed. (1981), Mind Design: Philosophy, Psychology, Artificial Intelligence. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  28. Haugeland, J. (1981), "Semantic Engines; An Introduction to Mind Design", in J. Haugeland, ed., Mind Design: Philosophy, Psychology. Artificial Intelligence. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, pp. 1-34.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  29. Hempel, C. G. (1965), Aspects of Scientific Explanation. New York, NY: The Free Press.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  30. Horsten, L. and H. Roelants (1995), "The Church-Turing Thesis and Effective Mundane Procedures", Minds and Machines 5, pp. 1-8.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  31. Kearns, J. (1997), 'Thinking Machines: Some Fundamental Confusions'. Minds and Machines 7, pp. 269-287. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  32. Kleene, S. C. (1967), Mathematical Logic. New York, NY: John Wiley & Sons, 1967.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  33. Newell, A. and H. Simon (1979), 'Computer Science as Empirical Inquiry: Symbols and Search', Communications of the ACM 19, p. 113-126; reprinted in Haugeland (1981), pp. 35-66. Page references are to the reprinted version.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  34. Rapaport, W. J. (1988), 'Syntactic Semantics: Foundations of Computational Natural Language Understanding', in J. Fetzer, ed., Aspects of Artificial Intelligence, Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 81-131.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  35. Searle, J. (1992), The Rediscovery of the Mind, Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  36. Stillings, N. A. et al. (1987), Cognitive Science: An Introduction. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  37. Thagard, P. (1995), 'Review of Barbara von Eckhardt, What is Cognitive Science?', Philosophy of Science 62, pp. 345-346.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  38. von Eckhardt, B. (1993), What is Cognitive Science? Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  39. von Neumann, J. (1958), The Computer and the Brain. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library

Index Terms

  1. Thinking and Computing: Computers as Special Kinds of Signs
    Index terms have been assigned to the content through auto-classification.

    Recommendations

    Comments

    Login options

    Check if you have access through your login credentials or your institution to get full access on this article.

    Sign in

    Full Access