Skip to main content
Log in

Sociality and the life–mind continuity thesis

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The life–mind continuity thesis holds that mind is prefigured in life and that mind belongs to life. The biggest challenge faced by proponents of this thesis is to show how an explanatory framework that accounts for basic biological processes can be systematically extended to incorporate the highest reaches of human cognition. We suggest that this apparent ‘cognitive gap’ between minimal and human forms of life appears insurmountable largely because of the methodological individualism that is prevalent in cognitive science. Accordingly, a twofold strategy is used to show how a consideration of sociality can address both sides of the cognitive gap: (1) it is argued from a systemic perspective that inter-agent interactions can extend the behavioral domain of even the simplest agents and (2) it is argued from a phenomenological perspective that the cognitive attitude characteristic of adult human beings is essentially intersubjectively constituted, in particular with respect to the possibility of perceiving objects as detached from our own immediate concerns. These two complementary considerations of the constitutive role of inter-agent interactions for mind and cognition indicate that sociality is an indispensable element of the life–mind continuity thesis and of cognitive science more generally.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Of course, strictly speaking phenomenology is concerned with one’s own lived experience, so it might appear strange that we want to generalize some of its insights to life as such. It is beyond the scope of this paper to argue for this claim more fully, except to point out that we do have second-person access to the experience of others (cf. Phenomenology of intersubjectivity), and that this can evidently include some other forms of life. Moreover, we can correlate our experience with our biological conditions and this enables us to justify from the third-person perspective that other organisms are likely to undergo similar experiences.

  2. “The ipseity is, of course, never reached: each aspect of the thing which falls to our perception is still only an invitation to perceive beyond it, still only a momentary halt in the perceptual process. […] What makes the ‘reality’ of the thing is therefore precisely what snatches it from our grasp. The aseity of the thing, its unchallengeable presence and the perpetual absence into which it withdraws, are two inseparable aspects of transcendence” (Merleau-Ponty 1945, p. 271).

References

  • Auvray, M., Hanneton, S., Lenay, C., & O’Regan, K. (2005). There is something out there: Distal attribution in sensory substitution, twenty years later. Journal of Integrative Neuroscience, 4(4), 505–521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Auvray, M., Lenay, C., & Stewart, J. (2009). Perceptual interactions in a minimalist virtual environment. New Ideas in Psychology, 27(1), 32–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barandiaran, X., Di Paolo, E. A., & Rohde, M. (2009). Defining agency: Individuality, normativity, asymmetry and spatio-temporality in action. Adaptive Behavior.

  • Beer, R. D. (2000). Dynamical approaches to cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4(3), 91–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boden, M. A. (2006). Of islands and interactions. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 13(5), 53–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2001). Mindware: An introduction to the philosophy of cognitive science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2003). Natural-born cyborgs: Minds, technologies, and the future of human intelligence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2005). Beyond the flesh: Some lessons from a mole cricket. Artificial Life, 11(1–2), 233–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher, H., & Di Paolo, E. A. (2007). Participatory sense-making: An enactive approach to social cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6(4), 485–507.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher, H., & Froese, T. (2009). On the role of social interaction in individual agency. Adaptive Behavior.

  • Di Paolo, E. A. (2005). Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4(4), 429–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. A. (2009). Extended life. Topoi, 28(1), 9–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. A., Rohde, M., & Iizuka, H. (2008). Sensitivity to social contingency or stability of interaction? Modelling the dynamics of perceptual crossing. New Ideas in Psychology, 26(2), 278–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. A., Rohde, M., & De Jaegher, H. (2009). Horizons for the enactive mind: Values, social interaction, and play. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne & E. A. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction: Towards a new paradigm for cognitive science. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, M. (1992). Human minds: An exploration. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, T., & De Jaegher, H. (2009). Enactive intersubjectivity: Participatory sense-making and mutual incorporation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. doi:10.1007/s11097-009-9136-4.

  • Froese, T. (2009). Hume and the enactive approach to mind. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 8(1), 95–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T. & Di Paolo, E. A. (2008), “Stability of coordination requires mutuality of interaction in a model of embodied agents”, in: M. Asada, et al. (eds.), From Animals to Animats 10: Proc. of the 10th Int. Conf. on Simulation of Adaptive Behavior, Berlin, Germany: Springer-Verlag, pp. 52–61

  • Froese, T., & Di Paolo, E. A. (2009). Modeling social interaction as perceptual crossing: An investigation into the dynamics of the interaction process. Connection Science.

  • Froese, T., & Ziemke, T. (2009). Enactive artificial intelligence: Investigating the systemic organization of life and mind. Artificial Intelligence, 173(3–4), 366–500.

    Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T., Virgo, N. & Izquierdo, E. (2007), “Autonomy: a review and a reappraisal”, in: F. Almeida e Costa et al. (eds.), Advances in Artificial Life: Proc. of the 9th Euro. Conf. on Artificial Life, Berlin, Germany: Springer-Verlag, pp. 455–464

  • Gallagher, S. (2001). The practice of mind: Theory, simulation, or primary interaction. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8(5–7), 83–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2008a). Intersubjectivity in perception. Continental Philosophy Review, 41(2), 163–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2008b). Direct perception in the intersubjective context. Consciousness and Cognition, 17(2), 535–543.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2008). The phenomenological mind: An introduction to philosophy of mind and cognitive science. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (1996). Spencer and Dewey on life and mind. In M. Boden (Ed.), The philosophy of artificial life (pp. 314–331). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1927). Sein und Zeit, trans. by: J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Being and time. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1929). Die Grundbegriffe der Metaphysik: Welt, Endlichkeit, Einsamkeit, trans. by: W. McNeill & N. Walker, The fundamental concepts of metaphysics: World, finitude, solitude. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserliana (Hua)

  • Husserliana I: Husserl, E. (1929). Cartesianische Meditationen und Pariser Vorträge, Den Haag, Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff, 1950; trans. by: D. Cairns, Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology, The Hague, Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff, 1960.

  • Husserliana IX: Husserl, E. (1925). Phänomenologische Psychologie. Vorlesungen Sommersemester 1925, Den Haag, Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff, 1962; trans. by: J. Scanlon, Phenomenological Psychology: Lectures, Summer Semester, 1925, The Hague, Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff, 1977.

  • Husserliana X: Husserl, E. (1893–1917). Zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewusstseins (1893–1917), Den Haag, Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff, 1966; trans. by: J. B. Brough, On the Phenomenology of the Consciousness of Internal Time (1893–1917), Dordrecht, Netherlands: Kluwer Academic, 1991.

  • Husserliana XIII: Husserl, E. (1905–1920). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Erster Teil: 1905–1920, Den Haag, Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973.

  • Husserliana XIV: Husserl, E. (1921–1928). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Zweiter Teil: 1921–1928, Den Haag, Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973.

  • Husserliana XV: Husserl, E. (1929–1935). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität. Texte aus dem Nachlass. Dritter Teil: 1929–1935, Den Haag, Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973.

  • Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1966). The phenomenon of life: Toward a philosophical biology. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1992). The burden and blessing of mortality. The Hastings Center Report, 22(1), 34–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1790). Kritik der Urteilskraft, trans. by: W. S. Pluhar, Critique of judgment. Indianapolis: Hacket Publishing Company. 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H. R., & Varela, F. J. (1987). The tree of knowledge: The biological roots of human understanding. Boston: Shambhala Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1945). Phénomènologie de la perception, trans. by: C. Smith, Phenomenology of perception. New York: Routledge & Kegan Paul. 1962.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1960). Les relations avec autrui chez l’enfant, Paris, France: Cours de Sorbonne, trans. by W. Cobb, “The Child’s Relations with Others”, in: M. Merleau-Ponty (1964), The primacy of perception and other essays on phenomenological psychology, the Philosophy of Art, History and Politics, J. M. Edie (Ed.) (pp. 96–155). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Moreno, A., & Etxeberria, A. (2005). Agency in natural and artificial systems. Artificial Life, 11(1–2), 161–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mossio, M., & Taraborelli, D. (2008). Action-dependent perceptual invariants: From ecological to sensorimotor approaches. Consciousness and Cognition, 17(4), 1324–1340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge: The MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petitmengin, C. (2006). Describing one’s subjective experience in the second person: An interview method for the science of consciousness. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 5(3–4), 229–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1967). Biologie et connaissance, Paris, France: Editions Gallimard; transl. as: Biology and knowledge: An essay on the relations between organic regulations and cognitive processes. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. 1971.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. (1943). L’Être et le néant, trans. by H. E. Barnes, Being and nothingness: An essay on phenomenological ontology. Oxon: Routledge. 2003.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, P., & Stewart, J. (2009). From autonomy to heteronomy (and back): The enaction of social life. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. doi:10.1007/s11097-009-9139-1.

  • Stewart, J. (1996). Cognition = life: Implications for higher-level cognition. Behavioral Processes, 35, 311–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, J. (2009). Foundational issues in enaction as a paradigm for cognitive science: From the origin of life to consciousness and writing. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne & E. A. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction: Towards a new paradigm for cognitive science. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2001). Empathy and consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8(5–7), 1–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2004). Life and mind: From autopoiesis to neurophenomenology. A tribute to Francisco Varela. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 3(4), 381–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M., Call, J., & Hare, B. (2003). Chimpanzees understand psychological states—The question is which ones and to what extent. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7(4), 153–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C., & Hubley, P. (1978). Secondary intersubjectivity: Confidence, confiding and acts of meaning in the first year. In A. Lock (Ed.), Action, gesture and symbol: The emergence of language (pp. 183–229). London: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1997). Patterns of life: Intertwining identity and cognition. Brain and Cognition, 34(1), 72–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1999). The specious present: A neurophenomenology of time consciousness. In J. Petitot, F. J. Varela, B. Pachoud & J.-M. Roy (Eds.), Naturalizing phenomenology: Issues in contemporary phenomenology and cognitive science (pp. 266–317). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., Maturana, H. R., & Uribe, R. (1974). Autopoiesis: The organization of living systems, its characterization and a model. BioSystems, 5, 187–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Foerster, H. (1976). Objects: Tokens for (Eigen-)Behaviors. ASC Cybernetics Forum, 8(3–4), 91–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Uexküll, J. (1934). “Streifzüge durch die Umwelten von Tieren und Menschen: Ein Bilderbuch unsichtbarer Welten”, trans. by: C. H. Schiller, “A stroll through the worlds of animals and men: a picture book of invisible worlds”. In C. H. Schiller (Ed.), Instinctive behavior: The development of a modern concept (pp. 5–80). New York: International Universities Press. Also appeared in: Semiotica, 89(4), 1992, pp. 319–391; 1957.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, A., & Varela, F. J. (2002). Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 97–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (1997), “Cognition’s Coming Home: the Reunion of Life and Mind”, in: P. Husbands & I. Harvey (eds.), Proc. of the 4th Euro. Conf. on Artificial Life, Cambridge: The MIT Press, pp. 10–19

  • Zahavi, D. (1996). Husserl und die transzendentale Intersubjektivität: Eine Antwort auf die sprachpragmatische Kritik, trans. by: E. A. Behnke, Husserl and Transcendental intersubjectivity: A response to the linguistic-pragmatic critique. Athens: Ohio University Press. 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2001). Beyond empathy: Phenomenological approaches to intersubjectivity. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8(5–7), 151–167.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2005). Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the first-person perspective. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zlatev, J. (2002). Meaning = Life (+Culture): An outline of a unified biocultural theory of meaning. Evolution of Communication, 4(2), 253–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tom Froese.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Froese, T., Di Paolo, E.A. Sociality and the life–mind continuity thesis. Phenom Cogn Sci 8, 439–463 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-009-9140-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-009-9140-8

Keywords

Navigation