Skip to main content
Log in

Asymmetric dominance, deferral, and status quo bias in a behavioral model of choice

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper proposes and axiomatically characterizes a model of choice that builds on the criterion of partial dominance and allows for two types of avoidant behavior: choice deferral and status quo bias. These phenomena are explained in a unified way that allows for a clear theoretical distinction between them to be made. The model also explains the strengthening of the attraction effect that has been observed when deferral is permissible. Unlike other models of status quo biased behavior, the one analyzed in this paper builds on a unique, reference-independent preference relation that is acyclic and generally incomplete. When this relation is complete, the model reduces to rational choice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The object \(\diamond \) is defined as something not belonging to X in Masatlioglu and Ok (2005). This minor difference in the two definitions is unimportant mathematically.

  2. Other interpretations have been adopted in the literature. For instance, Masatlioglu and Ok (2015) call \((A,\diamond )\) a problem without a status quo and (As) a problem with a status quo.

  3. This is so because the relation \(\succ \) is acyclic. Thus, if (1a) is not satisfied in \((A,\diamond )\), it must be because \(x\nsucc y\) for all \(x,y\in A\).

  4. Property \(\gamma \) is also commonly referred to as “Expansion” in the literature.

  5. Evidence for this effect was first reported in Iyengar and Lepper (2000).

  6. However, Ok et al. (2015) do analyze a model of choice in which certain feasible alternatives act as endogenous reference points that influence behavior by restricting the set of options over which the agent is maximizing his utility function.

References

  • Anderson, C. J. (2003). The psychology of doing nothing: Forms of decision avoidance result from reason and emotion. Psychological Bulletin, 129, 139–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Apesteguia, J., & Ballester, M. (2009). A theory of reference-dependent behavior. Economic Theory, 40, 427–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bewley, T. F. (2002). Knightian decision theory. Part I. Decisions in Economics and Finance, 25, 79–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bleichrodt, H. (2007). Reference-dependent utility with shifting reference points and incomplete preferences. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 51, 266–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bordallo, P., Gennaioli, N., & Shleifer, A. (2013). Salience and consumer choice. Journal of Political Economy, 121, 803–843.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buturak, G., & Evren, O. (2014). A theory of choice when “No Choice” is an option. Mimeo.

  • Clark, S. A. (1995). Indecisive choice theory. Mathematical Social Sciences, 30, 155–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Costa-Gomes, M., Cueva, C., & Gerasimou, G. (2014). Choice, deferral and consistency. School of Economics & Finance Discussion Paper 1416, University of St Andrews.

  • de Clippel, G., & Eliaz, K. (2012). Reason-based choice: A bargaining rationale for the attraction and compromise effects. Theoretical Economics, 7, 125–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dean, M. (2008). Status quo bias in large and small choice sets. Mimeo.

  • Dhar, R. (1997). Consumer preference for a no-choice option. Journal of Consumer Research, 24, 215–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dhar, R., & Simonson, I. (2003). The effect of forced choice on choice. Journal of Marketing Research, 40, 146–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Echenique, F., Saito, K., & Tserenjigmid, G. (2014). The perception-adjusted Luce model. Mimeo.

  • Gerasimou, G. (2015). Partially dominant choice. Economic Theory, forthcoming.

  • Greenleaf, E. A., & Lehmann, D. R. (1995). Reasons for substantial delay in consumer decision making. Journal of Consumer Research, 22, 186–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huber, J., Payne, J. W., & Puto, C. (1982). Adding asymmetrically dominated alternatives: Violations of regularity and the similarity hypothesis. Journal of Consumer Research, 9, 90–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurwicz, L. (1986). On the implementation of social choice rules in irrational societies. In W. P. Heller, R. M. Starr, & D. A. Starett (Eds.), Essays in Honor of Kenneth J. Arrow (Vol. I, chap. 4). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Iyengar, S. S., & Lepper, M. R. (2000). When choice is demotivating: Can one desire too much of a good thing? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79, 995–1006.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knetsch, J. L. (1989). The endowment effect and evidence of nonreversible indifference curves. American Economic Review, 79, 1277–1284.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knetsch, J. L., & Sinden, J. A. (1984). Willingness to pay and compensation demanded: Experimental evidence of an unexpected disparity in measures of value. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 99, 507–521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kreps, D. M. (2012). Microeconomic foundations I: Choice and competitive markets. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriesler, K., & Nitzan, S. (2008). Is context-based choice due to context-dependent preferences. Theory and Decision, 64, 65–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lombardi, M. (2009). Reason-based choice correspondences. Mathematical Social Sciences, 57, 58–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luce, M. F. (1998). Choosing to avoid: Coping with negatively emotion-laden consumer decisions. Journal of Consumer Research, 24, 409–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mandler, M. (2004). Status quo maintenance reconsidered: Changing or incomplete preferences? Economic Journal, 114, F518–F535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Masatlioglu, Y., & Ok, E. A. (2005). Rational choice with status quo bias. Journal of Economic Theory, 121, 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Masatlioglu, Y., & Ok, E. A. (2015). A canonical model of choice with initial endowments. Review of Economic Studies, 81, 851–883.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ok, E. A., Ortoleva, P., & Riella, G. (2015). Revealed (p)reference theory. American Economic Review, 105, 299–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reb, J. (2008). Regret aversion and decision process quality: Effects of regret salience on decision process carefulness. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 105, 169–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, W., & Zeckhauser, R. (1988). Status quo bias in decision making. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 1, 7–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheibenhenne, B., Greifeneder, R., & Todd, P. M. (2010). Can there ever be too many options? A meta-analytic review of choice overload. Journal of Consumer Research, 37, 409–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shafir, E., Simonson, I., & Tversky, A. (1993). Reason-based choice. Cognition, 11, 11–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simonson, I. (1989). Choice based on reasons: The case of attraction and compromise effects. Journal of Consumer Research, 16, 158–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1991). Loss aversion in riskless choice: A reference-dependent model. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 106, 1039–1061.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Shafir, E. (1992). Choice under conflict: The dynamics of deferred decision. Psychological Science, 3, 358–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zakay, D. (1984). “To Choose or not to Choose”: On choice strategy in face of a single alternative. American Journal of Psychology, 97, 373–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank Mark Dean, Robert Evans, Yusufcan Masatlioglu, Paola Manzini, Marco Mariotti, John Quah, Ran Spiegler, Jörg Stoye, audiences at Cambridge, Amsterdam, Queen Mary-London, St Andrews, EBIM 2010 (Bielefeld), EEA-ESEM 2011 (Oslo), SIRE-BIC 2012 (Edinburgh), and especially two referees of this journal for their very useful comments. Some of the material presented in this paper first appeared in a preliminary form in working papers titled “Rational indecisive choice” (2010) and “Asymmetric dominance, deferral and status quo bias in a model of choice with incomplete preferences” (2012). Partial financial assistance from the Scottish Institute for Research in Economics is gratefully acknowledged.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Georgios Gerasimou.

Appendices

Appendix A: Proofs

Proof of Proposition 1

The proofs that the axioms are necessary and that the preference relation \(\succ \) in the EPD model is unique are straightforward and omitted. For sufficiency, define \(\succ \) by \(x\succ y\) if \(C(\{x,y\},\diamond )=x\). Suppose \(x_1\succ x_2,\ldots ,x_k\succ x_1\) for some \(x_1,\ldots ,x_k\in X\). Let \(A:=\{x_1,\ldots ,x_k\}\). Without loss of generality, consider \((A,x_1)\in {\mathcal {S}}\). By assumption, \(C(A,x_1)\ne \emptyset \). Suppose \(x_1\in C(A,x_1)\). Then, \(x_k\succ x_1\) together with A1 implies \(C(\{x_1,x_k\},x_1)=x_k\), which violates A2. Suppose instead that \(x_j\in C(A,x_1)\) for some \(j\ne 1\). It follows from A1 that \(x_j\in C(A,\diamond )\). But since \(x_{j-1}\succ x_j\) holds by assumption, this also violates A2. Hence, \(x_j\not \in C(A,x_1)\) for all \(x_j\ne x_1\). It follows then that \(C(A,x_1)=\emptyset \), which is impossible by assumption. Hence, \(\succ \) is acyclic. Moreover, since all binary problems \((\{x,y\},\diamond )\) are included in \({\mathcal {S}}\), \(\succ \) is unique.

Consider now \((A,\diamond )\in {\mathcal {S}}\) and suppose \(C(A,\diamond )\ne \emptyset \). Let \(x\in C(A,\diamond )\). From A2, \(z\nsucc x\) for all \(z\in A\). From A5, \(x\succ y\) for some \(y\in A\). Moreover, if \(x\in A\) is such that \(x\succ y\) for some \(y\in A\) and \(z\nsucc x\) for all \(z\in A\), then applying A4 as above leads to \(x\in C(A,\diamond )\). It is obvious, finally, that \(C(A,\diamond )\ne \emptyset \) if \(C(A,\diamond )\) is as in (1a). Hence, (1a) holds.

Next, consider \((A,s)\in {\mathcal {S}}\). Suppose \(x\in C(A,s)\) for some \(x\ne s\). Assume to the contrary that there exists \(y\in A\) such that \(y\succ x\). It follows from \(x\in C(A,s)\), \(x\ne s\) and A1 that \(x\in C(A,\diamond )\). But since \(y\succ x\), this contradicts A2. Thus, \(x\in C(A,s)\) and \(x\ne s\) implies \(y\nsucc x\) for all \(y\in A\). Moreover, it follows from A3 that \(C(\{x,s\},s)\subset \{x,s\}\). Suppose \(x=C(\{x,s\},s)\). Then, A1 implies \(x\in C(\{x,s\},\diamond )\). From A3, \(x=C(\{x,s\},\diamond )\), or \(x\succ s\). Conversely, if C(As) consists of all \(x\in A\) such that \(y\nsucc x\) for all \(y\in A\) and \(x\succ s\), then A2 ensures that \(C(A,s)\ne s\). This establishes (1b).

For completeness, we will show how the axioms also imply (2) and (3). For the former, consider \((A,\diamond )\in {\mathcal {S}}\) and let \(x\nsucc y\) and \(y\nsucc x\) for all \(x,y\in A\). Assume, per contra, that \(w\in C(A,\diamond )\). From A3, \(C(A,\diamond )\subset A\). From A5, \(C(\{w,z\},\diamond )=w\) for some \(z\in A\setminus C(A,\diamond )\). Since \(w\nsucc z\) by assumption, this is a contradiction. Thus, \(C(A,\diamond )=\emptyset \). Conversely, let \(C(A,\diamond )=\emptyset \). Since \(\succ \) is acyclic, there exists \(x\in A\) such that \(z\nsucc x\) for all \(z\in A\). Suppose \(x\succ y\) for some \(y\in A\). Let \(A:=\{x,y,z_1,\ldots ,z_k\}\). Then, \(C(\{x,y\},\diamond )=x\) and either \(x\in C(\{x,z_i\},\diamond )\) or \(C(\{x,z_i\},\diamond )=\emptyset \) for all \(i\le k\). A4 implies \(x\in C(A,\diamond )\), a contradiction. This establishes (2).

Finally, to establish (3) suppose \((A,s)\in {\mathcal {S}}\) is such that \(y\nsucc s\) for all \(y\in A\) and assume to the contrary that \(x\in C(A,s)\) for some \(x\ne s\). It follows from above that \(x\succ s\), a contradiction. Since \(C(A,s)\ne \emptyset \), this implies \(s=C(A,s)\). Conversely, suppose \(C(A,s)=s\) and let \(x\succ s\) for some \(x\in A\). A1 implies \(C(\{x,s\},s)=x\). A2 then also implies \(s\not \in C(A,s)\), a contradiction. \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 2

The proof that (b) implies (a) is straightforward and omitted. For the converse, define the asymmetric relation \(\succ \) on X as in the preceding proof. It follows from A0 and A3 that \(x\succ y\) or \(y\succ x\) for all \(x,y\in X\). Hence, \(\succ \) is complete. Suppose \(x\succ y\), \(y\succ z\) and \(x\nsucc z\). Completeness implies \(z\succ x\), i.e., \(C(\{x,z\},\diamond )=z\). By assumption, \((\{x,y,z\},\diamond )\in Z\). Moreover, A0 implies \(C(\{x,y,z\},\diamond )\ne \emptyset \). If \(C(\{x,y,z\},\diamond )=x\), then \(z\succ x\) violates A2. The cases where \(C(\{x,y,z\},\diamond )=y\) and \(C(\{x,y,z\},\diamond )=z\) are similarly ruled out. Thus, \(x\succ z\) and \(\succ \) is also transitive, hence a strict linear order. As above, \(\succ \) is unique.

Consider \((A,\diamond )\in Z\). Suppose that \(C(A,\diamond )=x\) and let y be the \(\succ \)-maximal element of \(\succ \) in A. Assume to the contrary that \(x\ne y\). Completeness of \(\succ \) implies \(y\succ x\). Since \(C(A,\diamond )=x\) and \(y\in A\) by assumption, this violates A2. Thus, \(x=y\).

Next, let \((A,s)\in Z\) and define x and y as above. Consider the case where \(y\ne s\) first. By way of contradiction, suppose \(x\ne y\). Completeness of \(\succ \) and the definition of y imply \(y\succ x\) and \(y\succ s\). Let \(x\ne s\). From A1, \(x= C(A,s)\) implies \(x= C(A,\diamond )\). Since \(y\succ x\) and \(y\in A\) by assumption, \(x= C(A,\diamond )\) violates A2. Thus, \(x=s\). In this case, it follows from A1 and \(C(\{x,y\},\diamond )=y\) that \(C(\{s,y\},s)=y\). Since \(y\in A\) and \(s=x= C(A,s)\) by assumption, this violates A2. Thus, \(x=y\).

Consider finally the case where \(y=s\). Suppose \(x\ne y\). From the definition of y \((=s)\) one has \(s\succ x\). From the definition of x one also has \(C(A,s)=x\). Since \(x\ne s=y\), it follows from A1 and \(x=C(A,s)\) that \(x=C(A,\diamond )\). In view of \(s\succ x\) and \(s\in A\), this violates A2. Thus, \(x=y\) and (1) is established for all \((A,p)\in Z\). \(\square \)

Appendix B: Axiom independence

Let \(X=\{w,x,y\}\) and let \({\mathcal {S}}\) be the union of the following collections of sets:

$$\begin{aligned}&\Big \{(\{w\},\diamond ),(\{x\},\diamond ),(\{y\},\diamond ), (\{w,x\},\diamond ),(\{w,y\},\diamond ),(\{x,y\},\diamond ), (\{w,x,y\},\diamond )\Bigr \},\\&\quad \Big \{(\{w\},w),(\{w,x\},w),(\{w,y\},w),(\{w,x,y\},w) \Bigr \}, \\&\quad \Big \{(\{x\},x),(\{w,x\},x),(\{x,y\},x),(\{w,x,y\},x) \Bigr \}, \\&\quad \Big \{(\{y\},y),(\{w,y\},y),(\{x,y\},y),(\{w,x,y\},y). \Bigr \} \end{aligned}$$

Each of the examples below presents a set of choices that conforms with all but one of the axioms of Proposition 1. Axiom A1 is broken into A1a and A1b to reflect the former and the latter condition in the statement of the axiom, respectively.

Not A1a

$$\begin{aligned} C(\{w,x\},\diamond )= & {} C(\{x,y\},\diamond )=C(\{w,x,y\},\diamond )=x,\;\;\; C(\{w,y\},\diamond )=\emptyset \\ C(\{w,x\},w)= & {} C(\{w,x,y\},w)=x,\;\;\; C(\{w,y\},w)=w \\ C(\{w,x\},x)= & {} C(\{w,x,y\},x)=w,\;\;\; C(\{x,y\},x)=x \\ C(\{w,y\},y)= & {} C(\{w,x,y\},y)=y,\;\;\; C(\{x,y\},y)=x. \end{aligned}$$

Not A1b

$$\begin{aligned} C(\{w,x\},\diamond )= & {} \emptyset ,\;\;\; C(\{w,y\},\diamond )=C(\{w,x,y\},\diamond )=w,\;\;\; C(\{x,y\},\diamond )=x \\ C(\{w,x\},w)= & {} C(\{w,y\},w)=C(\{w,x,y\},w)=w, \\ C(\{w,x\},x)= & {} C(\{w,x,y\},x)=w,\;\;\; C(\{x,y\},x)=x \\ C(\{w,y\},y)= & {} C(\{x,y\},y)=C(\{w,x,y\},y)=y. \end{aligned}$$

Not A2

$$\begin{aligned} C(\{w,x\},\diamond )= & {} C(\{w,x,y\},\diamond )=w,\;\;\; C(\{w,y\},\diamond )=C(\{x,y\},\diamond )=y \\ C(\{w,x\},w)= & {} C(\{w,x,y\},w)=w,\;\;\; C(\{w,y\},w)=y \\ C(\{w,x,y\},x)= & {} x,\;\;\;C(\{w,x\},x)=w,\;\;\; C(\{x,y\},x)=y \\ C(\{w,y\},y)= & {} C(\{x,y\},y)=C(\{w,x,y\},y)=y. \end{aligned}$$

Not A3

$$\begin{aligned} C(\{w,x\},\diamond )= & {} \{w,x\},\;\;\; C(\{w,y\},\diamond )=w,\;\;\; C(\{x,y\},\diamond )=x,\;\;\; C(\{w,x,y\},\diamond )=\{w,x\}, \\ C(\{w,x\},w)= & {} C(\{w,y\},w)=C(\{w,x,y\},w)=w,\\ C(\{w,x\},x)= & {} \{w,x\},\;\;\; C(\{x,y\},x)=x,\;\;\; C(\{w,x,y\},x)=w\\ C(\{w,y\},y)= & {} C(\{w,x,y\},y)=w,\;\;\; C(\{x,y\},y)=x. \end{aligned}$$

Not A4

$$\begin{aligned} C(\{w,x\},\diamond )= & {} C(\{w,y\},\diamond )=\emptyset ,\;\;\; C(\{x,y\},\diamond )=x,\;\;\; C(\{w,x,y\},\diamond )=\emptyset , \\ C(\{w,x\},w)= & {} C(\{w,x,y\},w)=C(\{w,y\},w)=w \\ C(\{w,x\},x)= & {} C(\{w,x,y\},x)=C(\{x,y\},x)=x \\ C(\{w,y\},y)= & {} C(\{w,x,y\},y)=y,\;\;\; C(\{x,y\},y)=x. \end{aligned}$$

Not A5

$$\begin{aligned} C(\{w,x\},\diamond )= & {} C(\{x,y\},\diamond )=\emptyset ,\;\;\; C(\{w,x,y\},\diamond )=\{w,x\},\;\;\; C(\{w,y\},\diamond )=w \\ C(\{w,x\},w)= & {} C(\{w,x,y\},w)=C(\{w,y\},w)=w \\ C(\{w,x\},x)= & {} C(\{w,x,y\},x)=C(\{x,y\},x)=x \\ C(\{w,y\},y)= & {} C(\{w,x,y\},y)=w,\;\;\; C(\{x,y\},y)=y. \end{aligned}$$

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gerasimou, G. Asymmetric dominance, deferral, and status quo bias in a behavioral model of choice. Theory Decis 80, 295–312 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-015-9499-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-015-9499-7

Keywords

Navigation