Skip to main content
Log in

A Moderate Approach to Embodied Cognitive Science

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Many current programs for cognitive science sail under the banner of “embodied cognition.” These programs typically seek to distance themselves from standard cognitive science. The present proposal for a conception of embodied cognition is less radical than most, indeed, quite compatible with many versions of traditional cognitive science. Its rationale is based on two elements, each of which is theoretically plausible and empirically well-founded. The first element invokes the idea of “bodily formats,” i.e., representational codes primarily utilized in forming interoceptive or directive representations of one’s bodily states and activities. The second element appeals to wideranging evidence that the brain reuses or redeploys cognitive processes having different original uses. When the redeployment theme is applied to bodily formats of representation, they jointly provide for the possibility that body-coded cognition is a very pervasive sector of cognition.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A more complex representationalist analysis of one class of feelings, i.e., emotions, is offered by Prinz (2004). He holds that emotions are perceptions of the body, specifically, of bodily changes. He argues that emotions represent organism–environment relations, but they do so by perceiving bodily changes. In different terminology, organism–environment relations are said to be the “real” contents of emotions, and bodily changes are said to be their “nominal” contents (2004: 68). This is close enough, for our purposes, to treat emotions as embodied under our proposal; and Prinz certainly presents himself as an embodiment theorist.

  2. For additional supportive evidence of motor involvement in language understanding, see Pulvermuller and Fadiga (2010), Jirak et al. (2010), and Glenberg and Gallese (2011).

  3. Vignemont and Haggard (2008) pose the question of what specific representations are “shared” between sender and receiver in a mirror transaction. At what level of the hierarchical structure of the motor system do shared representations occur? This is a good question, to which they offer a complex array of interesting possible answers. However, the central question for present purposes does not concern the specific motoric level at which the observer’s representations replicate those of the actor, but whether any different cognitive tasks at all are undertaken by the observer that are distinct from those of the actor. And that question can be addressed without settling the one that concerns Vignemont and Haggard.

  4. In the experiment by Iacoboni et al. (2005) subjects observed a person in three kinds of conditions: an action condition, a context condition, and an intention condition. The intention condition was one that may have suggested an intention beyond that of merely grasping a cup: an intention either to drink tea or to clean up (after tea). This condition yielded a significant signal increase in premotor mirroring areas where hand actions are represented. This was interpreted by the researchers as evidence that premotor mirroring areas are involved in understanding the intentions of others. There is room for doubt about this interpretation. However, even if the enhanced mirroring activity during the intention condition did not constitute an intention attribution by the observer, it very plausibly did constitute a prediction or expectation of a future action by the portrayed individual. Since an action is not a mental state, predicting an action would not qualify as mindreading.

  5. For details of evidence about pain, see Avenanti et al. (2006), Shanton and Goldman (2010). For details about emotions like disgust and fear, see Goldman and Sripada (2005); Goldman (2006, chap. 6), Jabbi et al. (2007). The main “special” evidence for mirror-based mindreading in the case of emotions is evidence involving patients with paired deficits in experiencing and attributing the same emotion. For example, Calder et al. (2000) found such a pairing in patient NK, who had suffered insula and basal ganglia damage. On a questionnaire to probe the experience of disgust, NK’s score was significantly lower than that of controls. Similarly, in tests of his ability to recognize emotions from faces, NK showed a marked deficit in recognizing disgust but not other emotions. The natural inference (when conjoined with the Wicker et al. 2003 study) is that a normal subject who sees someone else’s disgust-expressive face undergoes a mirrored experience of disgust and uses it to recognize disgust in the other. This is why an impaired disgust system leaves a subject (selectively) unable to mindread disgust normally based on a facial (or vocal) expression, i.e., because he does not undergo a mirrored disgust experience.

  6. Gallese had previously advanced the concept of reuse, one of the core elements of the B-format approach, as the linchpin of an account of embodiment (Gallese 2007, 2008, 2010). Note, however, that reuse by itself is neither necessary nor sufficient for embodiment. It isn’t necessary because primary, or fundamental, uses of a B-format—which do not constitutes reuses—still qualify as instances of embodiment. It isn’t sufficient because there may be many cognitions that reuse non-bodily formats. Such reuses are not instances of embodied cognition. Gallese and Sinigaglia take notice of the latter point, writing “The notion of reuse, however, is not sufficient to explain the MM [mirror mechanism]” (2011: 513).

  7. Proffitt and colleagues often speak of influences on visual “experience,” and some might question whether this is fully supported by the evidence. The issue is whether their findings are merely post-perceptual phenomena rather than genuine perceptual phenomena. This matter has been tested and addressed in Witt et al. (2010). What they say seems quite re-assuring on this point, namely, that the findings do pertain to genuinely perceptual phenomena. The reader can judge for him/herself.

  8. I thank Dennis Proffitt, Michael Anderson, Vittorio Gallese, Frederique de Vignemont, and Lucy Jordan for helpful feedback on some of the main ideas in this paper. An earlier version of the material on Proffitt was presented to a workshop at the Australian National University. A talk based on the paper as a whole was presented at the Rutgers University Center for Cognitive Science. I am grateful to members of these groups for instructive criticisms.

References

  • Anderson, M.L. 2003. Embodied cognition: A field guide. Artificial Intelligence 149(1): 91–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, M.L. 2007a. Evolution of cognitive function via redeployment of brain areas. The Neuroscientist 13: 13–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, M.L. 2007b. Massive redeployment, exaptation, and the functional integration of cognitive operations. Synthese 159(3): 329–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, M.L. 2007c. The massive redeployment hypothesis and the functional topography of the brain. Philosophical Psychology 21(2): 143–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, J.R. 2007d. How can the human mind occur in the physical universe? Oxford University Press.

  • Anderson, M.L. 2008. Circuit sharing and the implementation of intelligent systems. Connection Science 20(4): 239–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, M.L. 2010. Neural reuse: A fundamental organizational principle of the brain. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33: 245–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andres, M., X. Seron, and E. Olivier. 2007. Contribution of hand motor circuits counting. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 19: 563–576.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Avenanti, A., I.M. Paluello, I. Bufalai, and S. Aglioti. 2006. Stimulus-driven modulation of motor-evoked potentials during observation of others’ pain. NeuroImage 32: 316–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L.W. 1999. Perceptual symbol systems. Behavioral and Brain sciences 22: 577–660.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L.W. 2008. Grounding cognition. Annual Review of Psychology 59: 617–645.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L.W., W.K. Simmons, A.K. Barbey, and C.D. Wilson. 2003. Grounding conceptual knowledge in modality-specific systems. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 7(2): 84–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergeron, V. 2007. Anatomical and functional modularity in cognitive science: Shifting the focus. Philosophical Psychology 20(2): 175–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bhalla, M., and D.R. Proffitt. 1999. Visual-motor recalibration in geographical slant perception. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 25: 1076–1096.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calder, A.J., J. Keane, F. Manes, N. Antoun, and A.W. Young. 2000. Impaired recognition and experience of disgust following brain injury. Nature Neuroscience 3: 1077–1078.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casasanto, D., and K. Dykstra. 2010. Motor action and emotional memory. Cognition 115(1): 179–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. 2008. Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, cognitive extension. Oxford University Press.

  • Clark, A., and D. Chalmers. 1998. The extended mind. Analysis 58(1): 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, A.D. 2002. How do you feel? Interoception: The sense of the physiological condition of the body. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 3: 655–666.

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G., and I. Ravenscroft. 2002. Recreative minds. Oxford University Press.

  • Dehaene, S. 2005. Evolution of human cortical circuits for reading and arithmetic: The ‘neuronal recycling’ hypothesis. In From monkey brain to human brain, eds. S. Dehaene, J.-R. Duhamel, M.D. Hauser, G. Rizzolatti, 131–157. MIT.

  • Dehaene, S. 2009. Reading in the brain. Viking.

  • Dehaene, S., and L. Cohen. 2007. Cultural recycling of cortical maps. Neuron 56: 384–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Durgin, F.H., J.A. Baird, M. Greenburg, R. Russell, K. Shaughnessy, and S. Waymouth. 2009. Who is being deceived? The experimental demands of wearing a backpack. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review 16(5): 964–969.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J.A. 1975. The language of thought. Harvard University Press.

  • Fodor, J.A., and Z. Pylyshyn. 1988. Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis. Cognition 28: 3–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fogassi, L., P.F. Ferrari, B. Gesierich, S. Rozzi, F. Chersi, and G. Rizzolatti. 2005. Parietal lobe: From action organization to intention understanding. Science 308: 662–667.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. 2005. Embodied simulation: From neurons to phenomenal experience. Phenomenology and Cognitive Science 4: 23–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. 2007. Before and below ‘theory of mind’: Embodied simulation and the neural correlates of social cognition. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, B 362: 659–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. 2008. Mirror neurons and the social nature of language: The neural exploitation hypothesis. Social Neuroscience 3(3–4): 317–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. 2010. Embodied simulation and its role in intersubjectivity. In The embodied self: Dimensions, coherence and disorders, eds. T. Fuchs, H.C. Sattel, P. Henningsen, 78–92. Schattauer.

  • Gallese, V., and A.I. Goldman. 1998. Mirror neurons and the simulation theory of mindreading. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 2: 493–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., and G. Lakoff. 2005. The brain’s concepts: The role of the sensory-motor system in conceptual knowledge. Cognitive Neuropsychology 22(3–4): 455–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., and C. Sinigaglia. 2011. What is so special about embodied simulation? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 15(11): 512–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gazzaniga, M.S., R.B. Ivry, and G.R. Mangun. 2002. Cognitive neuroscience, 2nd edition. Norton.

  • Glenberg, A.M., and V. Gallese. 2011. Action-based language: A theory of language acquisition, production and comprehension. Cortex

  • Glenberg, A.M., and M.F. Kaschak. 2002. Grounding language in action. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review 9: 558–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A.I. 1989. Interpretation psychologized. Mind and Language 4: 161–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A.I. 1992. In defense of the simulation theory. Mind and Language 7(1–2): 104–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A.I. 2006. Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mindreading. Oxford University Press.

  • Goldman, A.I. 2009. Mirroring, simulating, and mindreading. Mind and Language 24(2): 235–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A.I., and C.S. Sripada. 2005. Simulationist models of face-based emotion recognition. Cognition 94: 193–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A.I., and F. Vignemont. 2009. Is social cognition embodied? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 13(4): 154–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M., and D. Milner. 2004. Sight unseen. Oxford University Press.

  • Gordon, R.M. 1986. Folk psychology as simulation. Mind and Language 1: 158–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heal, J. 1986. Replication and functionalism. In Language, mind, and logic, ed. J. Butterfield. Cambridge University Press.

  • Hubbard, E.M., M. Piazza, P. Pinel, and S. Dehaene. 2005. Interaction between number and space in parietal cortex. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 6(6): 435–448.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S.L. 2005. The shared circuits hypothesis: A unified functional architecture for control, imitation, and simulation. In Perspectives on imitation: From neuroscience to social science, eds. S. Hurley N. Chater, 76–95. MIT.

  • Hurley, S.L. 2008. The shared circuits model: How control, mirroring and simulation can enable imitation, deliberation, and mindreading. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31(1): 1–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Iacoboni, M., I. Molnar-Szakacs, V. Gallese, G. Buccino, J.C. Mazziotta, and G. Rizzolatti. 2005. Grasping the intentions of others with one’s own mirror neuron system. PLoS Biology 3: 529–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jabbi, M., M. Swart, and C. Keysers. 2007. Empathy for positive and negative emotions in the gustatory cortex. NeuroImage 34: 1744–1753.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff, R. 1992. Languages of the mind: Essays on mental representation. MIT Press.

  • Jacob, P., and M. Jeannerod. 2006. The motor theory of social cognition: A critique. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 9(1): 21–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jirak, D., M.M. Menz, G. Buccino, A.M. Borghi, and F. Binkofski. 2010. Grasping language—A short story on embodiment. Consciousness and Cognition 19: 711–720.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keller, G.B., and R.H. Hahnloser. 2009. Neural processing of auditory feedback during vocal practice in a songbird. Nature 457: 187–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keysers, C., J.H. Kaas, and V. Gazzola. 2010. Somatosensation in social perception. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 11: 417–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krebs, J.R., and N.B. Davies. 1993. An introduction to behavioral ecology, 3rd edition . Blackwell.

  • Lakoff, G., and M. Johnson. 1980. Metaphors we live by. University of Chicago Press.

  • Lakoff, G., and M. Johnson. 1999. Philosophy in the flesh: The embodied mind and its challenge to western thought. Basic Books.

  • Linkenauger, S.A., V. Ramenzoni, and D.R. Proffitt. 2010. Illusory shrinkage and growth: Body-based rescaling affects the perception of size. Psychological Science 21(9): 1318–1325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milner, A.D., and M.A. Goodale. 1995. The visual brain in action. Oxford University Press.

  • O’Regan, J.K., and A. Noe. 2001. A sensorimotor approach to vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24(5): 939–973.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prather, J.F., S. Peters, S. Nowicki, and R. Mooney. 2008. Precise auditory-vocal mirroring in neurons for learned vocal communication. Nature 451: 249–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J.J. 2002. Furnishing the mind: Concepts and their perceptual basis. MIT Press.

  • Prinz, J.J. 2004. Gut reactions: A perceptual theory of emotion. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Proffitt, D.R. 2008. An action-specific approach to spatial perception. In Embodiment, ego-space, and action, eds. R.L. Katzky, B. MacWhinney, M. Behrmann. Psychology Press.

  • Proffitt, D.R. 2009. Affordances matter in geographical slant perception. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review 16(5): 970–972.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Proffitt, D.R., and S.A. Linkenauger. 2012. Perception viewed as a phenotypic expression. Tutorials in Action Science, eds. W. Prinz, M. Beisert, A. Herwig. MIT.

  • Pulvermuller, F. 2005. Brain mechanisms linking language and action. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 6: 576–582.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pulvermuller, F., and L. Fadiga. 2010. Active perception: Sensorimotor circuits as a cortical basis for language. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 11: 351–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., and L. Craighero. 2004. The mirror neuron system. Annual Reviews of Neuroscience 27: 169–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., and C. Sinigaglia. 2006. Mirrors in the brain: How our minds share actions and emotions. Oxford University Press.

  • Rizzolatti, G., and C. Sinigaglia. 2010. The functional role of the parieto-frontal mirror circuit: Interpretations and misinterpretations. Natural Reviews Neuroscience 11: 264–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., L. Fadiga, V. Gallese, and L. Fogassi. 1996. Premotor cortex and the recognition of motor actions. Cognitive Brain Research 3: 131–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roux, F.-E., S. Boetto, O. Sacko, F. Chollet, and M. Tremoulet. 2003. Writing, calculating, and finger recognition in the region of the angular gyrus: A cortical stimulation study of Gerstmann syndrome. Journal of Neurosurgery 99: 716–727.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schnall, S., J.R. Zandra, and D.R. Proffit. 2009. Direct evidence for the economy of action: Glucose and the perception of geographical slant. Perception 39: 464–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shanton, K., and A.I. Goldman. 2010. Simulation theory. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews, Cognitive Science. doi:10.1002/wcs.33.

  • Shapiro, L. 2011. Embodied cognition. Routledge.

  • Sheperd, S.V., J.T. Klein, R.O. Deaner, and M.L. Platt. 2009. Mirroring of attention by neurons in macaque parietal cortex. PNAS 106: 9489–9494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. 1995. Ten problems of consciousness. MIT.

  • Vignemont, F., and P. Haggard. 2008. Action observation and execution: What is shared? Social Neuroscience 3(3–4): 421–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weiskopf, D. 2007. Concept empiricism and the vehicles of thought. Journal of Consciousness Studies 14: 156–183.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wicker, B., C. Keysers, J. Plailly, J.-P. Royet, V. Gallese, and G. Rizzolatti. 2003. Both of us disgusted in my insula: The common neural basis of seeing and feeling disgust. Neuron 40: 655–664.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witt, J.K., and D.R. Proffitt. 2008. Action-specific influences on distance perception: A role for motor simulation. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Experimental Psychology 34: 1479–1492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witt, J.K., D.R. Proffitt, and W. Epstein. 2010. When and how are spatial perceptions scaled? Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 36(5): 1153–1160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alvin I. Goldman.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Goldman, A.I. A Moderate Approach to Embodied Cognitive Science. Rev.Phil.Psych. 3, 71–88 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-012-0089-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-012-0089-0

Keywords

Navigation