Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Beyond the Conflict: Religion in the Public Sphere and Deliberative Democracy

  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Traditionally, liberals have confined religion to the sphere of the ‘private’ or ‘non-political’. However, recent debates over the place of religious symbols in public spaces, state financing of faith schools, and tax relief for religious organisations suggest that this distinction is not particularly useful in easing the tension between liberal commitments to equality on the one hand, and freedom of religion on the other. This article deals with one aspect of this debate, which concerns whether members of religious communities should receive exemptions from regulations that place a distinctively heavy burden on them. Drawing on Habermas’ understanding of churches as ‘communities of interpretation’, we explore possible alternatives to both the ‘rule-and-exemption’ approach and the ‘neutralist’ approach. Our proposal rests on the idea of mutual learning between secular and religious perspectives. On this interpretation, what is required is (i) the generation and maintenance of public spaces in which there could be discussion and dialogue about particular cases, and (ii) evaluation of whether the basic conditions of moral discourse are present in these spaces. Thus deliberation becomes a touchstone for the building of a shared democratic ethos.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We use the term ‘reformist’ because their proposals are intended to develop the ideals of membership and participation without relinquishing the core presumptions of liberal democracy. Thus, behind the shared commitment to reformism lie different political philosophical backgrounds, such as communitarianism or republicanism.

  2. Some liberal authors have also recently drawn attention to the relevance of religion. In particular, Bou-Habib (2006) critically characterises religion as a ‘basic good’ or an ‘intense preference’. He argues that religious conduct can be a ‘derivative good’, with its value stemming from the integrity of the religious person. Liberal multiculturalism also concedes that some cultutal and religious exemptions are necessary in order to preserve other values such authonomy and equal respect. All these perspective register a tension between ‘public’ obligations and ‘private’ obligations deriving from religious membership.

  3. See Noonan (2005, pp. 103–110) for an overview of the characteristics of a deliberative democracy rooted in discourse ethics.

  4. This dichotomy between public and private spheres would be rejected both by defenders of religion in the public realm and by Habermas, through deliberative democracy, as we shall see later.

  5. The reclusion of religion to the conscience of the believer was in fact a triumph of the Protestant Reformation, which decided, based on theses such as the free interpretation of the Scriptures, that the relation between God and man was a direct one, through one’s conscience, and not through an institution or hierarchy, as held by Catholicism.

  6. Bader (1999, p. 602) expresses this idea forcefully: ‘The important thing, given the priority of democracy, should not be whether arguments are religious or secular but whether arguments, attitudes and practices are compatible with the principles, rights, culture, virtues, and good practices of social, democratic constitutionalism’.

  7. We wish to insist that following this argument would in no way imply the claim that religious norms and traditions must be respected per se and that the State must abstain from interfering in all religious practices. Of course, some of these practices must be considered manifestations of freedom of conscience which may clash with other basic political rights, but both are relevant for citizens and it is difficult to prioritise one over the other (Weithman 1995, p. 32). Here it is crucial to distinguish between practices such as the consumption of peyote in some religious Amerindian ceremonies or the ritual sacrifice of animals, which pose no harm to other people, and practices which attack the dignity and basic rights of people. Religious practices which lead to domestic violence, genital mutilation, sexual abuse or collective suicide, for example, must be prohibited by the State. ‘Here, criminal law should step in: priority for liberal democracy must be strong enough to legitimize public scrutiny and interference to sanction these practices effectively’ (Bader 2003a, p. 277).

  8. To address the response which has emerged from critical theory, we focus on Habermas’ (1996, 1998, 2008a, b) and Cortina’s (1993, 1995, 1998, 2001) works and thought.

  9. With the U principle, which establishes the conditions for discourse, one may distinguish norms which are morally valid, as each affected subject is obliged to accommodate himself to and understand the perspective of others before expressing his own interests. In other words, each must enter into dialogues whose objective is understanding and in which the participants take one another into consideration as valid interlocutors. Now, as we enter the territory of configuring a morally legitimate political space, one must take into account not only this principle, but also that in which juridical-political norms comply with the D principle. This then establishes that it is the actual participants in the discourse, those affected by the moral norm in question, who take on the role of protagonists through their active participation in the dialogue aimed at understanding. At the same time, one affirms that the types of reasons or judgements emitted are those which must be examined in each process of debate.

  10. The error here lies in considering that any interest is true and valid simply by virtue of being ‘mine’ or ‘ours’. For both models of political philosophy, the interest is a given. They forget how these interests were constructed. However, as Mead affirms, any process of individuation is a process of socialisation (Habermas 1972, 1975). Therefore, if the interests have been socially, culturally, or religiously constructed, the political sphere ought to incorporate deliberation concerning them, given that politics is inherent in the processes through which these interests have been formed (Habermas 1996, 1998, pp. 239–264).

  11. The republican concept of democracy is particularly vulnerable to this error, as it stems from the idea of a society which can self-organise as a whole. This overlooks the elements of social and cultural pluralism present in society, which ought to be seriously considered given that the interests and values intrinsic in such pluralism may conflict within the same community without any perspective for achieving consensus. One must not forget that the politically established right needs to be considered legitimate and ‘must be at least in harmony with moral principles that claim a general validity that extends beyond the limits of any legal community’ (Habermas 1998, p. 245).

  12. For the discussion on the Habermas’s position about the religion role and treatment in a Postsecular Societies see for example the Journal Constellations. 14 (2) with articles from Chambers (2007), Cooke (2007) and Lafont (2007).

  13. It is important to mention here that his position had previously been ambivalent, vacillating and on occasions ambiguous with regard to the relation between religion and reason. See Habermas (1987).

  14. Martha Minow too takes this line (2007, p. 825).

References

  • Audi, Robert. 1989. The separation of church and state and the obligations of citizenship. Philosophy and Public Affairs 18: 259–296.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, Robert. 1997. Liberal democracy and the place of religion in politics. In Religion in the public square. The place of religious convictions in liberal debate, ed. Audi Robert, and Nicholas Wolterstorff, 1–66. London: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, Robert, and Nicholas Wolterstorff. 1997. Religion in the public square. The place of religious convictions in liberal debate. London: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bader, Veit. 1999. Religious pluralism: Secularism or priority for democracy? Political Theory 27: 597–633.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bader, Veit. 2003a. Religious diversity and democratic institutional pluralism. Political Theory 31: 265–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bader, Veit. 2003b. Taking religious pluralism seriously: Arguing for an institutional turn. Introduction. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 6: 3–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barry, Brian. 2000. Culture and equality. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedi, Sonu. 2007. Debate: What is so special about religion? The dilemma of the religious exemption. Journal of Political Philosophy 15 (2): 235–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, Colin. 1996. Mutual respect and neutral justification. Ethics 197: 61–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bou-Habib, Paul. 2006. A theory of religious accommodation. Journal of Applied Philosophy 23 (1): 109–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, Gerard V. 1991. Beguiled: Free exemptions and the siren song of liberalism. Hofstra Law Review 20: 245–319.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chambers, Simone. 2007. How religion speaks to the agnostic: Habermas on the persistent value of religion. Constellations 14 (2): 210–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conill, Jesús. 2007. Racionalización religiosa y ciudadanía postsecular en perspectiva habermasiana. Pensamiento: Revista de investigación e información filosófica 63 (238): 571–581.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooke, Maeve. 2007. A secular state for a postsecular society? Postmetaphysical political theory and the place of religion. Constellations 14 (2): 224–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cortina, Adela. 1993. Ética aplicada y democracia radical. Madrid: Tecnos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cortina, Adela. 1995. Ética civil y religión. Madrid: PPC.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cortina, Adela. 1998. Hasta un pueblo de demonios. Ética pública y sociedad. Madrid: Taurus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cortina, Adela. 2001. Alianza y contrato. Política, ética y religión. Madrid: Trotta.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, Mark. 2004. Pluralising liberalism, liberalising pluralism. Res Publica 10: 449–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galeotti, Anna Elisabetta. 1993. Citizenship and equality: The place for toleration. Political Theory 21 (4): 585–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenawalt, Kent. 1990. Religious convictions and political choice: Some further thoughts. DePaul Law Review 39: 1019–1046.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gutmann, Amy, and Derek Thompson. 1990. Moral conflict and political consensus. Ethics 101 (1): 64–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1972. Knowledge and human interests. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1975. Legitimation crisis. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1987. The theory of communicative action, vol. 2. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1996. Between facts and norms. Contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1998. The inclusion of the other. Studies in political theory. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 2008a. Between naturalism and religion. Philosophical essays. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 2008b. La voz pública de la religión. Respuesta a Flores d’Arcais. Claves de razón práctica 180: 4–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hollenbach, David. 1993. Contexts of the political role of religion: Civil society and culture. San Diego Law Review 30: 877–901.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, Peter. 2004. Introduction: Law and disobedience. Res Publica 10: 319–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1988. Crítica de la razón pura. Madrid: Alfaguara.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lafont, Cristina. 2007. Religion in the public sphere: Remarks on Habermas’s conception of public deliberation in postsecular societies. Constellations 14 (2): 239–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, Jacob T. 1997. Classifying cultural rights. In Ethnicity and froup rightsed, ed. Ian Shapiro and Will Kymlicka, 22–66. Nomos XXXIX. New York: New York University Press.

  • Locke, John. 1999. Carta sobre la tolerancia. Ensayo y Carta sobre la tolerancia. Madrid: Alianza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marshall, William P. 1990. The case against the constitutionally compelled free exercise exemption. Case Western Law Review 40 (2): 357–412.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mate, Reyes. 2008. El debate Habermas—Flores d’Arcais: la religión en una sociedad postsecular. Claves de razón práctica 181: 28–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Minow, Martha. 2007. Should religious groups be exempt from civil rights laws? Boston Collage Law Review 48 (781): 781–849.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noonan, Jeff. 2005. Modernization, rights, and democratic society: The limits of Habermas’s democratic theory. Res Publica 11: 101–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quong, Jonathan. 2004. Disputed practices and reasonable pluralism. Res Publica 10: 43–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1996. Liberalismo político. Barcelona: Crítica.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1999. El derecho de gentes y ‘Una revisión de la idea de razón pública’. Barcelona: Crítica.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, William. 2004. Democracy, deliberation and disobedience. Res Publica 10: 353–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weithman, Paul J. 1991. The separation of church and state: Some questions for Professor Audi. Philosophy and Public Affairs 20 (1): 52–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weithman, Paul J. 1995. Contractualist liberalism and deliberative democracy. Philosophy and Public Affairs 24 (4): 314–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This article draws on research carried out with the support of the EuroEthos Research Project Project, funded under the European Commission’s 6th Framework Programme. Thanks to two anonymous referees for helpful comments on an earlier draft.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Elsa González.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

González, E., Lozano, J.F. & Pérez, P.J. Beyond the Conflict: Religion in the Public Sphere and Deliberative Democracy. Res Publica 15, 251–267 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-009-9093-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-009-9093-3

Keywords

Navigation