Skip to main content
Log in

The Knower Paradox in the light of provability interpretations of modal logic

  • Published:
Journal of Logic, Language and Information Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper propounds a systematic examination of the link between the Knower Paradox and provability interpretations of modal logic. The aim of the paper is threefold: to give a streamlined presentation of the Knower Paradox and related results; to clarify the notion of a syntactical treatment of modalities; finally, to discuss the kind of solution that modal provability logic provides to the Paradox. I discuss the respective strength of different versions of the Knower Paradox, both in the framework of first-order arithmetic and in that of modal logic with fixed point operators. It is shown that the notion of a syntactical treatment of modalities is ambiguous between a self-referential treatment and a metalinguistic treatment of modalities, and that these two notions are independent. I survey and compare the provability interpretations of modality respectively given by Skyrms, B. (1978, The Journal of Philosophy 75: 368–387) Anderson, C.A. (1983, The Journal of Philosophy 80: 338– 355) and Solovay, R. (1976, Israel Journal of Mathematics 25: 287–304). I examine how these interpretations enable us to bypass the limitations imposed by the Knower Paradox while preserving the laws of classical logic, each time by appeal to a distinct form of hierarchy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Anderson, C.A., 1983, “The Paradox of the Knower,” The Journal of Philosophy 80, 338–355.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N. and Kamp., H., 1989, “Self-reference, attitudes and paradox,” in Chierchia et al. (1989): 85–158.

  • Bicchieri, C. and Dalla Chiara, M.L., eds., 1992, Knowledge, Belief and Strategic Interaction, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Binmore, K. and Shin, H.S., 1992, “Algorithmic knowledge and game theory,” in Bicchieri and Dalla Chiara, pp. 141–154.

  • Boolos, G., 1993, The Logic of Provability, New York, Cambridge Unversity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boolos, G. and Sambin, G., 1991, “Provability: The emergence of a mathematical modality,” Studia Logica 50, 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chellas, B.F., 1980, Modal Logic: An Introduction, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, G., Partee, B. and Turner, R., eds., 1989, Properties, Types and Meaning, Vol. I, Foundational Issues, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publisher, Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cross, C.B., 2001a, “The Paradox of the Knower without epistemic closure,” Mind 110, 319–333.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cross, C.B., 2001b, “A theorem concerning syntactical treatments of non-idealized belief,” Synthese 129, 335–341.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cross, C.B., 2004, “More on the Paradox of the Knower without epistemic closure,” Mind 113, 109–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enderton, H.B., 1972, A Mathematical Introduction to Logic, San Diego, CA: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feferman, S., 1962, “Transfinite recursive progressions of axiomatic theories,” Journal of Symbolic Logic 27, 259–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H., 2002, “Saving the truth schema from paradox,” Journal of Philosophical Logic 31, 1–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, H. and Sheard, M., 1987, “An axiomatic approach to self-referential truth,” Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 33, 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gödel, K., 1933, “Eine Interpretation des intuitionistischen Aussagenkalküls,” translated in, Collected Works,Vol. 1, K. Gödel, S. Feferman et al., eds., New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henkin, L., 1952, “A problem concerning provability,” Journal of Symbolic Logic 17, 160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. and Montague, R., 1960, “A paradox regained,” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 1, 79–90, repr. in Montague (1974), 271–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koons, R., 1992, Paradoxes of Belief and Strategic Rationality, New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Löb, M.H., 1955, “Solution of a problem of Leon Henkin,” Journal of Symbolic Logic 20, 115–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGee, V., 1991, Truth, Vagueness and Paradox: An Essay on the Logic of Truth, Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R., 1963, “Syntactical treatments of modality, with corollaries on reflexion principles and finite axiomatizability,” Acta Philosophica Fennica 16, 153–67, repr. in Montague (1974), 286–302.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R., 1974, Formal Philosophy Selected Papers of Richard Montague, edited and with an introduction by R.H. Thomason, New Haven, Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perlis, D. and Subrahmanian, V., 1994, “Meta-languages, reflection principles and self-reference,” in Handbook of Logic in Artificial Intelligence and Logic Programming, Vol. II: Deduction Methodologies, D. Gabbay, C.J. Hogger and J.A. Robinson, eds., Oxford University Press, pp. 323–358.

  • Quine, W.V.O., 1940, Mathematical Logic, Revised Edn., Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1981.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V.O., 1953, “Three grades of modal involvement,” in The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 158–176.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinhardt, W.N., 1980, “Necessity predicates and operators,” Journal of Philosophical Logic 9, 437–450.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinhardt, W.N., 1986, “Epistemic theories and the interpretation of Gödel’s incompleteness theorems,” Journal of Philosophical Logic 15, 427–474.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richard, M., 1990, Propositional Attitudes, An Essay on Thoughts and How We Ascribe Them, New York, Cambridge.

  • Skyrms, B., 1978, “An immaculate conception of modality, or how to confuse use and mention,” The Journal of Philosophy 75, 368–387.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smoryński, C., 1985, Self-Reference and Modal Logic, New York: Springer Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smoryński, C., 1991, “The development of self-reference: Löb’s theorem,” in Perspectives on the History of Mathematical Logic, T. Drucker, ed., Boston, MA: Birkhäuser, pp. 110–133.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smullyan, R.M., 1986, “Logicians who reason about themselves,” in Reasoning About Knowledge, Proceedings of the TARK Conference, San Mateo, CA: Morgan Kaufman, pp. 341–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smullyan, R.M., 1992, Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorems, Oxford Logic Guides 19, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solovay, R., 1976, “Provability interpretations of modal logic,” Israel Journal of Mathematics 25, 287–304.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomason, R., 1977, “Indirect discourse is not quotational,” The Monist 60, 340–354.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomason, R., 1980, “A note on syntactical treatments of modality,” Synthese 44, 391–395.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, R., 1990, Truth and Modality for Knowledge Representation, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tymoczko, T., 1984, “An unsolved puzzle about knowledge,” Philosophical Quarterly 34, 437–458.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uzquiano, G., 2004, “The Paradox of the Knower without epistemic closure?,” Mind 113, 95–107.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Égré, P. The Knower Paradox in the light of provability interpretations of modal logic. J Logic Lang Inf 14, 13–48 (2004). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10849-004-6406-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10849-004-6406-y

Key words

Navigation