Skip to main content
Log in

The body in action

  • Regular article
  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article is about how to describe an agent’s awareness of her bodily movements when she is aware of executing an action for a reason. Against current orthodoxy, I want to defend the claim that the agent’s experience of moving has an epistemic place in the agent’s awareness of her own intentional action. In “The problem,” I describe why this should be thought to be problematic. In “Motives for denying epistemic role,” I state some of the main motives for denying that bodily awareness has any epistemic role to play in the content of the agent’s awareness of her own action. In “Kinaesthetic awareness and control,” I sketch how I think the experience of moving and the bodily sense of agency or control are best described. On this background, I move on to present, in “Arguments for epistemic role,” three arguments in favour of the claim that normally the experience of moving is epistemically important to one’s awareness of acting intentionally. In the final “Concluding remarks,” I round off by raising some of the worries that motivated the denial of my claim in the first place.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a discussion of the distinction between enabling and justificatory roles, see Falvey (2000).

  2. For such a position, see Jeannerod and Pacherie (2004) and Jeannerod (1999).

  3. This type of motivation finds a clear expression in Anscombe (2000, esp. pp. 53–54). See also Moran (2004). Similar views are expressed by Gallagher and Marcel (1999).

  4. Among people endorsing the claim that bodily movements are neutral with respect to agency we find O’Shaughnessy (1973), Hornsby (1980, Chaps. 1–3), Armstrong (1981, pp. 74f.), McGinn (1982, Chap. 5), Ginet (1990, p. 23), Pietroski (1998, § 3), and Lowe (2000, Chap. 9). For the idea that action-awareness is non-inferential, see Anscombe (2000, p. 54), Hossack (2003), and O’Brien (2003).

  5. For this idea, see O’Brien (2003). Even though I think this motive is completely unfounded, I include it here because it is present in the literature. There are, however, good reasons not to accept it. Firstly, there is no phenomenological warrant for the claim that the sensory experience is delayed. We simply do not kinaesthetically experience our movements as chasing after the actual movement. Secondly, there might even be evidence for the fact that “sensory” experience of moving precedes the actual movement (in terms of overt limb movement or muscle contraction). Some “sensory” awareness might be generated in advance by some neural sensory-prediction mechanism. For these reasons I don’t take idea of time lack to constitute any real challenge to my proposal, and will not return to it again.

  6. For references, see note 4.

  7. For a brief review of some of the relevant literature, see Jeannerod and Pacherie (2004). The basic idea is that voluntary movements have a characteristic motoric fingerprint in terms of distinctive patterns of acceleration and deceleration.

  8. The qualia view of agency is endorsed by Ginet (1990) and Hossack (2003). Recent neurophenomenological theories of agency come close to a qualia view; for example, Gallagher (2000) and Gallagher (2005, Chap. 8).

  9. For a similar continuum conception, see Husserl (1973, Beilage 25).

  10. In my use of the term “sense of agency” I follow the usage of recent discussions by, e.g., Gallagher (2000). It refers to the agent’s experience of bodily activity.

  11. See Frankfurt (1978).

  12. See Della Sala et al. (1994), Marchetti and Della Sala (1998). In the latter article they write: “The patients are aware of the bizarre and potentially hazardous behaviour of their hand but cannot inhibit it. They often refer to the feeling that one of their hands behaves as if it has a will of its own, but never deny that this capricious hand is part of their own body” (p. 196). And later: “[The patients] are always well aware of their odd behaviour and consciously try to overrule the unwanted action by appeasing the wayward hand” (p. 202). For a different and conflicting account, see Riddoch et al. (2000, esp. p. 607).

  13. For this point, see Haggard (2005).

  14. For similar analysis of ownership, see Martin (1995) and Brewer (1995).

  15. I agree with Jeannerod and Pacherie (2004) that ordinarily problems of action-attribution or ownership do not arise for our own ordinary motor acts. But I disagree with their Rylean conclusion that this must mean that ordinarily motor acts are experienced as belonging to nobody. The explicit form of self-attribution rests on an implicit sense of ownership. For ideas congenial to mine, see Bermúdez (1998, Chaps. 5–7), and Zahavi (2005, Chap. 5).

  16. Admittedly, here it is not kinaesthetic awareness but merely kinaesthetic information that plays the role of enabling intentional action. I think this move is defensible because if information alone can do the job, then it seems as if by assigning awareness only a enabling role this might in the end make it completely epiphenomenal. Awareness does no real work here. This points to another important problem. When it comes to awareness of aspects of our intentional behaviour – and surely the active bodily movement is an aspect – what sense does it actually make to distinguish between an enabling and an epistemic function? I think none. For the sake of argument I have followed my opponent in making the distinction; but in the end it should be dropped.

  17. For a related proposal, see Peacocke (2003).

References

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957/2000). Intention. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. (1981). The nature of mind. Brighton: The Harvester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez, J. L. (1998). The paradox of self-consciousness. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, B. (1995). Bodily awareness and the self. In J.L. Bermúdez, A. Marcel, & N. Eilan (Eds.), The body and the self. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cole, J. (1995). Pride and a daily marathon. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Della Sala, S., Marchetti, C., & Spinnler, H. (1994). The anarchic hand: a fronto-mesial sign. In F. Boller and J. Grafman (Eds.), Handbook of neuropsychology. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Falvey, K. (2000). Knowledge in intention. Philosophical Studies, 99, 21–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1978). The problem of action. American Philosophical Quarterly, 15(2), 157–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2000). Philosophical conceptions of the self: Implications for cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4(1), 14–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Marcel, A. (1999). The self in contextualized action. In S. Gallagher & J. Shear (Eds.), Models of the self. Thorverton: Imprint Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginet, C. (1990). On action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haggard, P. (2005). Conscious intention and motor cognition. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 9(6), 290–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hornsby, J. (1980). Actions. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hossack, K. (2003). Consciousness in act and action. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 2, 187–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1973). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität II, Husserliana XIV. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M. (1999). To act or not to act: Perspectives on the representation of action. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 52A, 1–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M., & Pacherie, E. (2004). Agency, simulation and self-identification. Mind and Language, 19(2), 113–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2000). An introduction to the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcel, A. (1998). Blindsight and shape perception: Deficit of visual consciousness or of visual function? Brain, 121, 1565–1588.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marchetti, C., & Della Sala, S. (1998). Disentangling the alien and anarchic hand. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, 3(3), 191–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. (1995). Bodily awareness: A sense of ownership. In J. L. Bermúdez, A. Marcel, & N. Eilan (Eds.), The body and the self. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (1982). The character of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moran, R. (2004). Anscombe on ‘Practical Knowledge’. In J. Hyman & H. Steward (Eds.), Agency and action: Royal institute of philosophy supplement 55 (pp. 43–68).

  • O’Brien, L. (2003). On knowing one’s own actions. In J. Roessler & N. Eilan (Eds.), Agency and self-awareness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Shaughnessy, B. (1973). Trying (as the mental “pineal gland”). The Journal of Philosophy, 70(13), 365–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Shaughnessy, B. (1980). The will, II. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (2003) Action: Awareness, ownership, and knowledge. In J. Roessler & N. Eilan (Eds.), Agency and self-awareness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perenin, M. T., & Rossetti, Y. (1996). Residual grasping in a hemianopic field: a further dissociation between perception and action. Neuroreport 7, 793–799.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pietroski, P. (1998) Actions, adjuncts, and agency. Mind 107(425), 73–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pisella et al. (2000). An ‘automatic pilot’ for the hand in human posterior parietal cortex: Toward reinterpreting optic ataxia. Nature Neuroscience 3, 729–736.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riddoch, M. J., Humphreys, G., & Edward, M. G. (2000). Visual affordances and object selection. In S. Monsell & J. Driver (Eds.), Control of Cognitive Processes (Attention and Performce XVIII). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2005) Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the first-person perspective. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author wishes to thank Johannes Roessler, Dan Zahavi, and two anonymous reviewers for helpful discussions and criticism of earlier versions of the paper. The research for this paper was funded by the Danish National Research Foundation and the Carlsberg Foundation.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thor Grunbaum.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Grunbaum, T. The body in action. Phenom Cogn Sci 7, 243–261 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-007-9072-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-007-9072-0

Keywords

Navigation