Skip to main content
Log in

Vagueness: Why Do We Believe in Tolerance?

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The tolerance principle, the idea that vague predicates are insensitive to sufficiently small changes, remains the main bone of contention between theories of vagueness. In this paper I examine three sources behind our ordinary belief in the tolerance principle, to establish whether any of them might give us a good reason to revise classical logic. First, I compare our understanding of tolerance in the case of precise predicates and in the case of vague predicates. While tolerance in the case of precise predicates results from approximation, tolerance in the case of vague predicates appears to originate from two more specific sources: semantic indeterminacy on the one hand, and epistemic indiscriminability on the other. Both give us good and coherent grounds to revise classical logic. Epistemic indiscriminability, it is argued, may be more fundamental than semantic indeterminacy to justify the intuition that vague predicates are tolerant.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. When those restrictions would fail, some of those accounts accept the Dummettian view that vague predicates are simply inconsistent, see [8] and [22, 32].

  2. Fara’s articulation of the epistemological question differs somewhat from the present one, but this does not bear on the main distinction at stake here.

  3. See [18, 21, 45] on the consideration of such examples.

  4. Regarding the French version of the proverb, we are certainly ready to concede that a given glass recipient has a determinate volume. The English version of the proverb is more interesting in a way, because there is arguably no absolutely determinate load that counts as the maximum load the camel can support. The fact remains, however, that whatever the finite range in which this maximum would fall, its upper bound can be outweighed by any small quantity.

  5. Standard rules differ, in that they round to the even round value, see [28]. The specificity of the rounding rule chosen does not matter however in what follows, we may even consider nonsymmetric approximation intervals, and adapt our analysis accordingly.

  6. The analysis may also be related to the central gap account of tolerance defended by Pagin in [32], where the tolerance principle is pragmatically restricted by the assumption that individuals in the domain do not fall within a central gap whose size is at least that of a tolerance level fixed by the context for each vague predicate.

  7. See [46]: “Fortunately, ‘thin’ is not governed by the tolerance principle; it is governed by the margin for error principle (!), which generates no sorites paradox”. Williamson’s margin of error principle implies that we cannot know where the cutoff lies. According to Williamson, it is a verificationist bias that urges us, from the impossibility to know P x and ¬P y of any x and y such that x P y, to believe that there are no such x and y.

  8. See particularly [50] and [33] on permissible disagreement in borderline cases. The resulting notion of indeterminacy fits what Smith calls plurivaluationism, what [13] calls second level indeterminacy, or what [41] calls open-texture (in a sense compatible with but weaker than Waismann’s original sense), to characterize the compatibility of the meaning of an expression with a multiplicity of different verdicts. This notion of semantic indeterminacy is compatible with stronger notions, such as what Eklund calls first-order indeterminacy, for when a predicate is semantically gappy, but it is not mandated by it.

  9. The notion of indifference is sometimes judged even more fundamental than that of indiscriminability, for cases in which we are in a position to make a distinction, but in which the difference is judged practically irrelevant. Arguably, however, the notion of indiscriminability is more explanatory of the phenomenon of tolerance. [21] writes that a difference between 41 and 40 chimpanzees is as discriminable in principle as a difference between 5 and 6 chimpanzees, but practically less relevant when ascribing “large” to a community of chimpanzees. This is correct, but it would be less easily discriminable if presented perceptually. He also considers that “large” is not a perceptual predicate in that example, but this is controversial. Our mental representation of numerosities, relative to some given unit, and even for more clearly nonphenomenal predicates such as “rich” or “expensive”, may remain highly dependent on our perceptual ability to discriminate between quantities. See [20] and [16] for arguments in that direction.

  10. See in particular [3] for a defense of gap principles against D-introduction, and work in progress by P. Pagin opposing the same rule, based on the assumption that “determinately” operators behave as intensifiers. For a recent assessment of higher-order gap principles, see also [52].

  11. See among others [9, 10, 23, 29, 30, 51] or [37]. For example, [30] write: “One existential claim we surely do not want to make is this: there is an n such that the nth tile definitely looks red and the (n+1)st tile definitely does not look red. Such a claim would allege a justifiable distinction where there is no significant difference”. Likewise, [9] writes: “‘no single grain makes a difference between a heap and a non-heap’. If this means: no single grains makes a decisive difference – takes you from a clear heap to a clear non-heap – then it is true. If it means: no single grain at all makes any difference to heapdom, then it is false”. Even [42]’s defense of closeness, the idea that close cases should receive close semantic values, may be reanalyzed in terms of gaps, as the idea that the assignment of opposite semantic values to P a and P b implies that a and b should be sufficiently far. See [11] and [4] for further discussion.

  12. See particularly [52], [36] and [4] for a defense of this inferentialist conception.

  13. Incidentally, it would also fail in the trivalent reinterpretation of TCS presented for instance in [4], where closeness is defined directly in terms of distance between semantic values, rather than as a relation over objects proper. This feature is not essential to the trivalent account, however.

  14. Monotonicity is what [18] calls an internal penumbral connection. I take the term “monotonicity” from [31]. It is used by [21] in the same sense. [2] uses the term “scalarity”.

  15. Compare with [52]’s talk of the “good” semantic values a sentence can take.

  16. See particularly [33] and [41] for related views about tolerance and semantic competence.

References

  1. Borel, E. (1907). Un paradoxe économique: le sophisme du tas de blé et les vérités statistiques. La Revue du Mois, 4, 688–699. English translation by P. Égré and E. Gray, in Erkenntnis(79), 1081-1088, 2014 [An economic paradox: the sophism of the heap of wheat and statistical truths].

    Google Scholar 

  2. Burnett, H. (2015). Gradability in natural language: Logical and grammatical foundations. Oxford studies in semantics and pragmatics. Oxford University Press.

  3. Cobreros, P. (2011). Supervaluationism and Fara’s argument concerning higher-order vagueness In Egré, P., & Klinedinst, N. (Eds.), Vagueness and language use (pp. 207–221). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Cobreros, P., Egré, P., Ripley, D., & van Rooij, D. (2014). Vagueness, truth and permissive consequence In Achouriotti, D., Galinon, H., & Martinez, J. (Eds.), Unifying the Philosophy of Truth. Berlin: Springer. In press.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Cobreros, P., Egré, P., Ripley, D., & van Rooij, R. (2012). Tolerance and mixed consequence in the s’valuationist setting. Studia Logica, pp. 1–23.

  6. Cobreros, P., Egrė, P., Ripley, D., & van Rooij, R. (2012). Tolerant, classical, strict. The Journal of Philosophical Logic, pp. 1–39.

  7. van Deemter, K. (1996). The sorites fallacy and the context-dependence of vague predicates In Kanazawa, M., Piñon, C., & de Swart H. (Eds.), Quantifiers, deduction, and context(pp. 59–86). Stanford: CSLI Publications.

  8. Dummett, M. (1975). Wang’s paradox. Synthese, 30(3-4), 301–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Edgington, D. (1997). Vagueness by degrees In Keefe, R., & Smith, P. (Eds.), Vagueness: A reader(pp. 294–316). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Egré, P. (2009). Soritical series and Fisher series In Hieke, A., & Leitgeb, H. (Eds.), Reduction: Between the mind and the brain(pp. 91–115). Hessen: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Egré, P. (2011). Perceptual ambiguity and the sorites In Nouwen, R., van Rooij, R., Sauerland, U., & Schmitz, H. (Eds.), Vagueness in communication(pp. 64–90). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  12. Egré, P., & Barberousse, A. (2014). Borel on the heap. Erkenntnis, 79, 1043–1079.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Eklund, M. (2005). What vagueness consists in. Philosophical Studies, 125(1), 27–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Fara, D. (2000). Shifting sands: an interest-relative theory of vagueness. Philosophical Topics, 28(1), 45–81. Originally published under the name “Delia Graff”.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Fara, D. (2003). Gap principles, penumbral consequence, and infinitely higher-order vagueness In Beall, J. (Ed.), Liars and heaps: New essays on paradox(pp. 195–221). London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Feigenson, L., Dehaene, S., & Spelke, E. (2004). Core systems of number. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8(7), 307–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Field, H. (2010). This magic moment: Horwich on the boundaries of vague terms In R. Dietz, & S. Moruzzi (Eds.), Cuts and clounds: Essays on the nature and logic of vagueness (pp. 200–208). London: Oxford University Press.

  18. Fine, K. (1975). Vagueness, truth, and logic. Synthese, 30, 265–300.

  19. Frege, G. (1879). Begriffschrift, Halle.

  20. Fults, S. (2011). Vagueness and scales In Egré, P., & Klinedinst, N. (Eds.), Vagueness and language use(pp. 25–50). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Gaifman, H. (2010). Vagueness tolerance and contextual logic. Synthese, 174(1), 5–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Gómez-Torrente, M. (2011). The sorites, linguistic preconceptions and the dual picture of vagueness In Dietz, R., & Moruzzi, S. (Eds.), Cuts and clouds(pp. 228–253). London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Greenough, P. (2003). Vagueness: A minimal theory. Mind, 112(446), 235–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Hobbs, J. (2000). Half orders of magnitude, KR-2000 Workshop on Semantic Approximation, Granularity, and Vagueness. Citeseer.

  25. Hyde, D. (1997). From heaps and gaps to heaps of gluts. Mind, 106(424), 641–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Kamp, H. (1981). The paradox of the heap. Aspects of Philosophical Logic, pp. 225–277.

  27. Kennedy, C. (2011). Vagueness and comparison In Egré, P., & Klinedinst, N. (Eds.), Vagueness and language use (pp. 73–97). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Kirkup, L., & Frenkel, B. (2006). An introduction to uncertainty in measurement. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  29. Lassiter, D. (2011). Vagueness as probabilistic linguistic knowledge In R. Nouwen, R. van Rooij, & H.-C. Schmitz (Eds.), Vagueness in communication(pp. 127–150). Berlin: Springer.

  30. McGee, V., & McLaughlin, B. (1995). Distinctions without a difference. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 33(S1), 203–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Nouwen, R. (2011). Degree modifiers and monotonicity In Egré, P., & Klinedinst, N. (Eds.), Vagueness and language use(pp. 146–164). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Pagin, P. (2011). Vagueness and domain restriction In Egré, P., & Klinedinst, N. (Eds.), Vagueness and language use (pp. 283–307). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Raffman, D. (1994). Vagueness without paradox. Philosophical Review, 103(1), 41–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Rescher, N. (1969). Many-valued logic. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Ripley, D. (2013). Sorting out the sorites In Tanaka, K., Berto, F., & Mares, E. (Eds.), Paraconsistency: Logic and applications(pp. 329–323). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  36. Ripley, D. (2013). Paradoxes and failures of cut. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91(1), 139–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. van Rooij, R. (2012). Vagueness, tolerance, and non-transitive entailment In Cintrula, P., Fermueller, C., Godo, L., & Hàjek, P. (Eds.), Understanding vagueness: Logical, philosophical and linguistic perspectives(pp. 205–222). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Russell, B. (1923). Vagueness. The Australasian Journal of Psychology and Philosophy, 1(2), 84–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Sauerland, U., & Stateva, P. (2011). Two types of vagueness In Egré, P., & Klinedinst, N. (Eds.), Vagueness and language use(pp. 121–145). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Schiffer, S. (2003). The things we mean. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  41. Shapiro, S. (2006). Vagueness in context. London: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  42. Smith, N.J.J. (2008). Vagueness and degrees of truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  43. Sorensen, R. (2001). Vagueness and contradiction. London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Weber, Z. (2010). A paraconsistent model of vagueness. Mind, 119(476), 1025–1045.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. Weber, Z., & Colyvan, M. (2011). A topological sorites. The Journal of Philosophy, 107(6), 311–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  46. Williamson, T. (1992). Vagueness and ignorance. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 66, 145–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. Williamson, T. (1994). Vagueness. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Wright, C. (1976). Language-mastery and the sorites paradox In Evans, G., & McDowell, J. (Eds.), Truth and meaning. New York: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Wright, C. (1992). Is higher-order vagueness coherent? Analysis, 52(3), 129–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. Wright, C. (1995). The epistemic conception of vagueness. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 33(S1), 133–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Zardini, E. (2008). A model of tolerance. Studia Logica, 90(3), 337–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  52. Zardini, E. (2013). Higher-order sorites paradox. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 42(1), 25–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Frank Veltman and Jeff Horty for their invitation to contribute this paper. I am indebted to Heather Burnett, Pablo Cobreros, Laurence Goldstein, David Ripley, Robert van Rooij and Frank Veltman for comments and discussions, to Laurence Goldstein and his students for a memorable conversation in a caf´e in Paris in 2013, and to audiences and colleagues at seminars held in Paris and NYU. Thanks to the European Research Council under the European Community’s Seventh Framework Program (FP7/2007-2013), to the project ‘Borderlineness and Tolerance’ (FFI2010-16984), Ministerio de Economia y Competitividad, Government of Spain, and to grants ANR-10-LABX-0087 IEC and ANR-10-IDEX-0001-02 PSL*.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Paul Égré.

Additional information

I dedicate this paper to the memory of Laurence Goldstein (1947-2014).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Égré, P. Vagueness: Why Do We Believe in Tolerance?. J Philos Logic 44, 663–679 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-015-9352-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-015-9352-z

Keywords

Navigation