Skip to main content
Log in

Husserl’s philosophy of mathematics: its origin and relevance

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Husserl Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper offers an exposition of Husserl's mature philosophy of mathematics, expounded for the first time in Logische Untersuchungen and maintained without any essential change throughout the rest of his life. It is shown that Husserl's views on mathematics were strongly influenced by Riemann, and had clear affinities with the much later Bourbaki school.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, e.g., Richard Tieszen’s Mathematical Intuition.

  2. The manuscripts on which is based Einleitung in die Logik und Erkenntnistheorie date from 1906–1907, thus, from the years of the transcendental turn. See on this issue the editorial introduction to Husserl’s Die Idee der Phänomenologie. The manuscripts on which is based Logik und allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie are of the transcendental phenomenology years

  3. Although, as pointed out in footnote 40, constructivism is perfectly compatible with transcendental phenomenology, one cannot say that it survived the transcendental turn—in the same sense in which one cannot say that a person born in 1960 “survived” the Second World War—, because it was never propounded by Husserl and certainly not before the transcendental turn.

  4. See A I 35, p. 11.

  5. A I 35, p. 12.

  6. Ibid.

  7. Ibid., pp. 17–18.

  8. Ibid., p. 17.

  9. A I 35, p. 25.

  10. Ibid., pp. 47–48.

  11. Ibid., p. 48.

  12. Ibid., p. 56.

  13. Ibid., p. 57.

  14. “Husserl’s Epistemology of Mathematics and the Foundation of Platonism in Mathematics,” Husserl Studies 4, No, 2, 1987, reprinted in Claire Ortiz Hill and Guillermo E. Rosado Haddock, Husserl or Frege?: Meaning, Objectivity and Mathematics, pp. 221–239.

References

  1. Bachelard, S. (1957). La Logique de Husserl. Paris: PUF.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Bourbaki, N. (1949). Foundations of mathematics for the working mathematician. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 14(4), 1–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Bourbaki, N. (1950). The architecture of mathematics. American Mathematical Monthly, 57, 221–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Bourbaki, N. (1966). ÉlÉments des MathÉmatiques: ThÉorie des Ensembles, Fascicule XVII. Paris: Hermann.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Bourbaki, N. (1966). ÉlÉments des MathÉmatiques: ThÉorie des Ensembles, Fascicule XXII. Paris: Hermann.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Cantor, G. Gesammelte Abhandlungen mathematischen und philosophischen Inhalts, 1932, reprint, Georg Olms, Hildesheim 1966.

  7. Carnap, R. Der Raum, Kant-Studien (Ergänzungsheft 56) 1922, reprint Topos Verlag, Vaduz 1991.

  8. Carnap, R. Der logische Aufbau der Welt, 1928, third edition, Felix Meiner 1961.

  9. Carnap, R. Logische Syntax der Sprache, 1934, expanded English edition, Routledge, London 1937, reprint, Open Court, Chicago et al., 2003.

  10. Dahlstrom, Daniel O. (Ed.) (2003). Husserl’s Logical Investigations, Kluwer: Dordrecht.

  11. Da Silva, J. J. (1998). Husserl’s conception of logic. Manuscrito, XXII(2), 367–387.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Da Silva, J. J. (2000). Husserl’s two notions of completeness. Synthese, 125, 417–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Da Silva, J. J. (2000). The many senses of completeness. Manuscrito, XXIII (2), 41–60.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Field, H. (1989). Realism, Mathematics and Modality. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Fisette, D. (Ed.) (2003). Husserl’s Logical Investigations Reconsidered, Kluwer: Dordrecht.

  16. Frege, G. Begriffschrift, 1879, reprint Georg Olms, Hildesheim 1964.

  17. Frege, G. Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik, 1884, Centenarausgabe, Felix Meiner, Hamburg 1986.

  18. Frege, G. Grundgesetze der Arithmetik I, 1893, II, 1903, reprint in one volume Georg Olms 1962.

  19. Gödel, K. Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme I. 1931, reprint with a parallel English translation in Kurt Gödel, Collected Works I, 1986, pp. 144–195.

  20. Hill, C. O. Incomplete Symbols, Dependent Meanings and Paradox. In Daniel, O., Dahlstrom (Eds.), Husserl’s Logical Investigations. pp. 69–93.

  21. Hill, C. O., & Rosado Haddock, G. E. Husserl or Frege?: Meaning, objectivity and mathematics. Open Court, Chicago & La Salle 2000, paperback edition 2003.

  22. Husserl, E. Über den Begriff der Zahl, 1887, reprinted as Appendix A in Husserliana XII, 1970, pp. 289–339.

  23. Husserl, E. Philosophie der Arithmetik, 1891, Husserliana XII, M. Nijhoff, The Hague 1970.

  24. Husserl, E. Besprechung von E. Schröder, ‘Vorlesungen über die Algebra der Logik I’, 1891, reprinted in Aufsätze und Rezensionen (1890–1910), Husserliana XXII, 1979, pp.3–43.

  25. Husserl, E. Logische Untersuchungen, 1900–1901, Husserliana XVIII (1975) & XIX (1984), M.␣Nijhoff, The Hague.

  26. Husserl, E. (1974). Formale und transzendentale Logik, 1929, Husserliana XVII. The Hague: M. Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Husserl, Ed. (1958). Die Idee der Phänomenologie, Husserliana II. The Hague: M. Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Husserl, E. (1979). Aufsätze und Rezensionen (1890–1910), Husserliana XXII. The Hague: M.␣Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Husserl, E. (1983). Studien zur Arithmetik und Geometrie, Husserliana XXI. The Hague: M.␣Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Husserl, E. (1984). Einleitung in die Logik und Erkenntnistheorie Husserliana XXIV. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Husserl, E. (1996). Logik und allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie, Husserliana XXX. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Husserl, E. (1975). Introduction to the Logical Investigations. The Hague: M. Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Husserl, Edmund. (2003). Alte und neue Logik: Vorlesungen 1908/09. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Husserl, E. Manuskript A I 35 (α) 1912, (β) 1920 und später.

  35. Kant, I. Kritik der reinen Vernunft 1781, 2nd edn. 1787, reprint of both versions, edited by R.␣Schmidt, Felix Meiner, Hamburg 1930, 3rd edn. 1990.

  36. Mac Lane, S. (1971). Categories for the Working Mathematician. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Mac Lane, S. (1986). Mathematics: Form and Function. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Majer, U. (1997). Husserl and Hilbert on completeness: A neglected chapter in early twenty century foundation of mathematics. Synthese, 110, 37–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Mancosu, P., & Ryckman, T.A. (2002). Mathematics and phenomenology: The correspondence between O. Becker and H. Weyl’. Philosophia Mathematica, 10(2), 130–202.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Riemann, B. Über die Hypothesen, welche der Geometrie zugrunde liegen, 1867, third edition, Berlin 1923, reprint, Chelsea, New York 1973.

  41. Rosado Haddock, G. E. (1973). Edmund Husserls Philosophie der Logik und Mathematik im Lichte der gegenwärtigen Logik und Grundlagenforschung, (Diss.), Bonn.

  42. Rosado Haddock, G. E. (1987). Husserl’s Epistemology of Mathematics and the Foundation of Platonism in Mathematics. Husserl Studies 4, No. 2, reprint in Claire, O. Hill & Guillermo E. Rosado Haddock, Husserl or Frege?: Meaning, Objectivity and Mathematics. pp. 221–239.

  43. Rosado Haddock, G. E. (1997). Husserl’s relevance for the philosophy and foundations of mathematics. Axiomathes, VIII(1–3), 125–142.

  44. Rosado Haddock, G. E. (2000). The structure of the prolegomena. Manuscrito, XXIII(2), 61–99.

  45. Rosado Haddock, G. E. Review of Edmund Husserl, Alte und neue Logik: Vorlesungen 1908/09. forthcoming in Husserl Studies.

  46. Schmit, R. (1981). Husserls Philosophie der Mathematik, Bouvier, Bonn.

  47. Scholz, E. (1980). Geschichte des Mannigfaltigkeitsbegriffs von Riemann bis Poincaré, Boston.

  48. Schuhmann, E., & Scuhmann, K. (2001) Husserl’s Manuskripte zu seinem Göttinger Doppelvortrag von 1901. Husserl Studies, 7, 87–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. Schuhmann, K. (1977). Husserl-Chronik. The Hague: M. Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Tarski, A. Der Wahrheitsbegriff in den formalisierten Sprachen 1935 (expanded version of the Polish original 1933), English translation in Alfred Tarski, Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics 1956, second edition, Hackett, Indiana 1983, pp. 152–278.

  51. Tieszen, R. (1989). Mathematical Intuition. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Torretti, R. (1978). Philosophy of Geometry from Riemann to Poincaré, Reidel, Dordrecht.

  53. Weyl, H. Das Kontinuum, 1918, reprint New York, Chelsea 1960, 1973.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Guillermo E. Rosado Haddock.

Appendix

This Appendix , based on the last chapter of my dissertation—see references—, discusses a still unpublished manuscript of Husserl, Manuscript AI 35, which I read in the Husserl Archives in Cologne in 1971 or 1972. I hereby thank the Husserl Archives in Cologne for having allowed me to read the manuscript while I was working on my dissertation. So far as I know, Claire O. Hill is the only other Husserl scholar that has referred in print—in her paper mentioned in the references—to this valuable manuscript.

Appendix

In the recent literature on Husserl’s views on mathematicsFootnote 2 the tendency already mentioned in footnote 40 to associate Husserl with different variants of constructivism, which, due to the apparent affinities of Husserl’s later trascendental phenomenology with Kant’s trascendental idealism would look very plausible, has experienced a sort of revitalization. However, as already mentioned, the fact of the matter is that both in his 1929 Formale und transzendentale Logik and other recently published courses contemporary with his trascendental turn or later,Footnote 3 there is no sign of any constructivism. Husserl’s views on mathematics remained the same after the trascendental turn. Although this is difficult to swallow by traditional phenomenologists, it represents no problem for those like the present author, who coincide with Carnap in seeing the phenomenological reduction as a purely methodological device. Thus, Platonism survives the trascendental turn.Footnote 4

In our dissertation of 1973, however, we discussed an extensive manuscript of Husserl, which we read in the Husserl Archives in Cologne, in which Husserl seriously considered constructivism. The manuscript, titled “The Paradoxes” and with the inscription A I 35, consists of two parts, namely, part α, dated 1912, and β, dated 1920. In the 1912 part of the manuscript Husserl is concerned with different ways to solve Russell’s paradox—or better: Zermelo-Russell’s—and similar paradoxes. Husserl bases his discussion on two important points, namely: (i) Not every meaning is fullfilable in a possible intuition; e.g., a round quadrangle can be thought, but cannot be intuited, there is no sensible or categorial intuition of it; (ii) One has to distinguish between different levels of language, thus, modifying a little Husserl’s example,Footnote 5 a proposition (or name) of a proposition S is of a level immediatly higher than S. We have here the nucleus of a theory of types. As Husserl makes it clear,Footnote 6 the Russell set would simply be a countersense. Moreover Husserl arguesFootnote 7 that membership in a set is an example of what he calls relations of essences, and in such relations the members cannot be identical. Beginning on p. 13 of the manuscript, Husserl speaks also about sets constructible from the axioms and definitions. As Husserl points out,Footnote 8 one should not ascribe an extension (or set) to all general concepts. As an example he mentionsFootnote 9 that the mere something in general of formal ontology, on which all formal ontological fundamental concepts are based, does not have any extension. Husserl considers other less palatable solutions in the first part of the manuscript, like the possibility of considering the notion of set as a special case of the notion of a whole, but what is important is that, as he states on p. 25 of the manuscript,Footnote 10 from the fact that we can speak about all sets does not follow that the totality of sets is a set, in the same sense that from the fact that we can speak about all possibilities does not follow that the totality of all possibilities is a possibility.

Contrary to what I sustained in my dissertation, and even though Husserl uses the expression “contructible” on pp. 12–13, the whole discussion of Husserl in part α of the manuscript is perfectly compatible with his philosophy of mathematics as presented in Logische Untersuchungen, especially if we consider his epistemology of mathematics of the second part of the Sixth Logical Investigation, in which he offers an iterative constitution of mathematical objects in categorial intuition. Such a view is clearly related to the views of his friends Cantor and Zermelo on the iterative notion of set, which is not to be related with constructivisms of Kantian or Brouwerian, or any other sort.

The case of part β of the manuscript is somewhat different. It dates from 1920, two years after the publication of Hermann Weyls Das Kontinuum. Weyl and his wife had been students of Husserl and were life-long friends of him. It seems that the publication of Weyl’s book, in which a mild constructivism was propounded, as well as the personal contact with his much younger friend, exerted a momentary influence on Husserl, which reflected itself in the second part of the manuscript. In this manuscript Husserl tries to show that the way to avoid the paradoxes consists in a constructive axiomatization of set theory. More explicitly, he stresses that a manifold is to be understood as a “constructively (definite) characterized region of objects, which remains (materially) undetermined, whose objects can be constructed by the iteration into infinity of definitely formed operations, and whose axioms must be so chosen as to found a priori such constructibility.”Footnote 11 Thus, for Husserl in part β of the manuscript, the doctrine of manifolds should be “the mathematical discipline of the possible constructible infinities” and its task should be “to construct a priori the possible forms of such infinities as constructive systems.”Footnote 12 With respect to Russell’s—better Zermelo-Russell’s—Paradox, Husserl saysFootnote 13 that it should not be assumed that concepts like that of the set of all sets that do not contain themselves as members have a totality, i.e., a set as extension, and that what such a paradox shows is that there is still no logic of sets in general. Moreover, Husserl addsFootnote 14 that sets should be demonstrably constructible with respect to all its members, and that mathematics must furnish an existence proof of each and every set. Husserl is, however, not explicit enough with respect to his notion of constructibility. It is only clear that he requires an existence proof of each set. An interesting question here is whether Husserl’s theory of manifolds and, in general, of mathematical objects required some revision on the basis of these constructivistic leanings of 1920, since, as we have shown elsewhere,Footnote 15 neither Russell’s nor Cantor’s sets can be obtained in the iterative hierarchy of mathematical objects propounded in the Sixth Logical Investigation. The fact of the matter is that in his later Formale und transzendentale Logik there is no explicit mention of such a restriction to constructible manifolds. Thus, either Weyl’s impact on Husserl was of short duration or he was convinced that his original philosophy of mathematics, together with his epistemology of mathematics, in which his iterative hierarchy of mathematical objects is inserted, were enough to prevent the paradoxes. These alternative explanations are by no means exclusive, and most probably both are correct.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Rosado Haddock, G.E. Husserl’s philosophy of mathematics: its origin and relevance. Husserl Stud 22, 193–222 (2006). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10743-006-9010-y

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10743-006-9010-y

Keywords

Navigation