Skip to main content

Confirmation, Explanation and Acceptance

  • Chapter

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series in Philosophy ((PSSP,volume 4))

Abstract

Contemporary epistemology owes much to Chishoim’s efforts to develop a unified theory of perceiving, knowing and believing, and his work has given considerable impetus to investigations of the connections among such locutions as ‘acceptable’, ‘evident’ and ‘probable’. Chisholm has suggested that it is reasonable for a person to believe or accept any proposition that is more probable than not in relation to the totality of what he or she knows,1 and many philosophers have agreed with him in this. Indeed, a number of them have wanted to base a theory of rational acceptance on some fairly well-established confirmation theory, and clearly it would be extremely useful for both epistemology and philosophy of science if there were some reasonably straightforward correlation between probability or confirmation and rational acceptance. There are times when we wish to say that evidence warrants accepting certain sentences as true, where these sentences are not deductive consequences of the evidence, and not merely that the evidence confirms the sentences or makes them probable, perhaps to some degree or other.

The author wishes to express gratitude to the Canada Council for support of research related to this paper. John Heintz, J. J. Macintosh and Robert Ware read an earlier draft and made helpful comments.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. R. M. Chisholm, Theory of Knowledge, Prentice-Hall, 1966, p. 19. See also his Perceiving, Cornell University Press, 1957, Chapters 1 and 2.

    Google Scholar 

  2. See, for example, R. M. Chisholm, Perceiving: A Philosophical Study,16; C. G. Hempel, ‘Deductive-Nomological vs. Statistical Explanation’, in Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science,Vol. III, ed. by Feigl and Maxwell, Minneapolis, 1962, pp. 163–166; K. Lehrer, ‘Knowledge and Probability’, The Journal of Philosophy 61 (1964), 368–372; I. Levi, ‘Deductive Cogency in Inductive Inference’, The Journal of Philosophy 62 (1964), 68–77; F. Schick, ‘Three Logics of Belief’, in M. Swain, ed., Induction, Acceptance, and Rational Belief,Dordrecht-Holland, pp. 6–26; and R. C. Sleigh, Jr., ‘A Note on Some Epistemic Principles of Chisholm and Martin’, The Journal of Philosophy 61 (1964), 216–218. Much of the first three sections of the paper surveys results already available in the literature. This is done with a view to eliciting some connections and drawing parallels that have not, so far as I know, been explicitly pointed out. The proof given in the text is essentially Lehrer’s, in the article cited above.

    Google Scholar 

  3. H. Kyburg, ‘A Further Note on Rationality and Consistency’, The Journal of Philosophy 60 (1963), 463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. This paradox of belief may be viewed as a generalization of the paradox of the preface, discussed by A. N. Prior in A Budget of Paradoxes, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1971, pp. 84–89. Prior attributes formulation of the paradox to D. C. Makinson, Analysis 25 (1964), 205–7.

    Google Scholar 

  5. This condition was originally stated by H. Smokier in ‘The Equivalence Condition’, American Philosophical Quarterly 4, (1967), 300–307. One can easily show that certain initially plausible conditions taken together lead to a violation of NC. The clearest example is probably the combination of special consequence, converse consequence and entailment conditions. Consider H1. It is a consequence of, and so, by the converse consequence and entailment conditions, confirms Hi.H2. But, given the special consequence condition, and also given that H2 is likewise a consequence of H1.H2, we have the result that Hi confirms H2, no matter what the content of Hi or H2 may be. For further discussion of some of these conditions see below, and also my ‘Goodman, Wallace, and the Equivalence Condition’, The Journal of Philosophy 64 (1967), 271–280, and ‘Confirmation and Adequacy Conditions’, Philosophy of Science 38 (1971), 361–368.

    Google Scholar 

  6. C. G. Hempel, ‘Studies in the Logic of Confirmation’, Mind 54 (1945), 1–26 and 97–121; reprinted in Hempel’s Aspects of Scientific Explanation,New York, 1965, pp. 3–46. All other references to this article are to this reprinting.

    Google Scholar 

  7. R. Carnap, Logical Foundations of Probability, 2nd edn., Chicago, 1962, pp. 476–78 (hereafter LFOP); see also K. Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery, New York, 1961, p. 374.

    Google Scholar 

  8. See N. Goodman, Fact, Fiction and Forecast, third edn, Indianapolis, 1973, Chapter 4.

    Google Scholar 

  9. See M. Hanen, ‘Confirmation and Adequacy Conditions’, Philosophy of Science 38 (1971), 361–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. An exception may be the Equivalence Condition, which is valid for Carnap’s explicatum. But see J. Wallace, ‘Goodman, Logic, Induction’, The Journal of Philosophy 63 (1966), 310–328, Goodman’s ‘Comments’, same journal, 331, and my ‘Goodman, Wallace, and the Equivalence Condition’, cited in n.15. I shall have something to say about some general considerations relevant to this problem later.

    Google Scholar 

  11. The notion of ‘the contrary of a hypothesis’ employed here is the one explained by Goodman, Fact, Fiction and Forecast,Chapter 1, fn. 2 and 9. See also I. Scheffler, The Anatomy of Inquiry,New York, 1963, pp. 286–91.

    Google Scholar 

  12. See R. Eberle, D. Kaplan, and R. Montague, ‘Hempel and Oppenheim on Explanation’, Philosophy of Science 28 (1961), 418–28; D. Kaplan, ‘Explanation Revisited’, same journal and volume, 429–36; and J. Kim. ‘Discussion: On the Logical Conditions of Deductive Explanation’, same journal 30 (1963), 286–91.

    Google Scholar 

  13. I use to stand for ‘inductively supports’. The example is Salmon’s in his ‘Consistency, Transitivity and Inductive Support’, Ratio 7 (1965), 165–9.

    Google Scholar 

  14. W. Salmon, Statistical Explanation and Statistical Relevance, Pittsburgh 1971, p. 56.

    Google Scholar 

  15. R. B. Braithwaite, Scientific Explanation, Cambridge University Press, 1953. The relevant section is reprinted in B. Brody (ed.), Readings in the Philosophy of Science, Prentice Hall, 1970, p. 62.

    Google Scholar 

  16. M. Martin, ‘Confirmation and Explanation’, Analysis 32 (1972), 167–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. G. Harman, ‘Induction’, in M. Swain (ed.) Induction, Acceptance, and Rational Belief See also A. Goldman, ‘A Causal Theory of Knowing’, The Journal of Philosophy 64 (1967), 357–72. Not all Gettier-type examples involve overt or conscious reasoning, but Harman has argued quite persuasively (in the article cited, and in his Thought,Princeton University Press, 1973) that inference is nonetheless present. The following is Harman’s version of a typical Gettier-type example, the example actually owing to Lehrer

    Google Scholar 

  18. Some arguments against acceptance rules can be found in Y. Bar-Hillel, ‘The Ac- ceptance Syndrome’, in L Lakatos (ed.), The Problem of Inductive Logic, North Holland, Amsterdam, 1968; R. Carnap, ‘Replies and Systematic Expositions’, in P. A. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, Open Court, 1963; and R. Jeffrey, ‘Valuation and Acceptance of Scientific Hypotheses’, Philosophy of Science 23, 237–46. Contrary views are expressed by H. Kyburg, ‘The Rule of Detachment in Inductive Logic’, in L Lakatos, The Problem of Inductive Logic, pp. 98–119, and I. Levi, Gambling With Truth, Knopf, New York, 1967. For a Bayesian view, see L. J. Savage, The Foundations of Statistics, Wiley, New York, 1954, and for the Neyman-Pearson approach a good source is J. Neyman and E. S. Pearson, Joint Statistical Papers, University of California Press, Berkeley, 1967. Hugues LeBlanc and Ron Giere have convinced me that philosophers need to pay more attention to this latter approach.

    Google Scholar 

  19. An example might be the rule proposed by R. Schwartz, I. Scheffler, and N. Goodman in ‘An Improvement in the Theory of Projectibility’, The Journal of Philosophy 67 (1970), 605–8.

    Google Scholar 

  20. R. Hilpinen, Rules of Acceptance and Inductive Logic, Amsterdam, 1968.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1975 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht-Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hanen, M. (1975). Confirmation, Explanation and Acceptance. In: Lehrer, K. (eds) Analysis and Metaphysics. Philosophical Studies Series in Philosophy, vol 4. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-9098-8_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-9098-8_6

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-277-1193-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-9098-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics