Skip to main content
Log in

The Metaphysics of Causal Models

Where’s the Biff?

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper presents an attempt to integrate theories of causal processes—of the kind developed by Wesley Salmon and Phil Dowe—into a theory of causal models using Bayesian networks. We suggest that arcs in causal models must correspond to possible causal processes. Moreover, we suggest that when processes are rendered physically impossible by what occurs on distinct paths, the original model must be restricted by removing the relevant arc. These two techniques suffice to explain cases of late preëmption and other cases that have proved problematic for causal models.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. More sophisticated counterfactual accounts, such as David Lewis’s influence theory (2000), do manage to account for cases such as Billy and Suzy, but this success appears to be in virtue of closely tracking the symptoms of causation, rather than the causal relation itself. Consequently, the account remains vulnerable to counterexamples (Schaffer 2001).

  2. It is not clear who coined the term, but it is strongly associated with D. M. Armstrong. The first occurrence in print of which we are aware is Lewis (2004). Leading biff theorists have been David Fair (1979), Wesley Salmon (1984), and Phil Dowe (2000).

  3. Causal models have been elegantly explained for a philosophical audience by Christopher Hitchcock (2001). Here we give only a very brief review of models, and direct unfamiliar readers to Hitchcock’s paper.

  4. We here ignore the subtle differences between Halpern and Pearl’s and Hitchcock’s analyses of token causation in causal models. See Korb et al. (2005) for a more thoroughgoing attempt to analyse token causation in terms of processes. Here we aim simply to illustrate the benefits of incorporating the metaphysics of causal processes into our theory of modelling.

  5. See Woodward and Hitchcock (2003) and Korb et al. (2005: 5).

  6. Hitchcock himself does not offer a model for this case, but implies that he too would use a model like that given in Fig. 2.

  7. Note we are using “fact” to refer to something like truths, and thus as things that can have truthmakers. Not everyone adopts this terminology, as for some—such as Russell—“fact” refers to the truthmakers themselves.

  8. Important historical examples of the struggle to account for negative truths are Russell (1972: 67–72) and Wittgenstein (1922: §2.06). More recently, see Molnar (2000).

  9. For instance, it could be said that the event of the rock being in Suzy’s hand at t′ is incompatible with Suzy’s having thrown the rock at t. And moreover, the event of the rock being in Suzy’s hand at t′′ is incompatible with the bottle’s having smashed, because given the laws and facts about Suzy’s throwing powers, she could not have thrown the rock so as to smash the bottle, and retrieve the rock again in such a short time.

  10. In the first, it is a process that runs from Suzy’s catch to the ball being in her hand at a later time. In the second, a process that runs from the ball flying past Suzy at t to the later smash.

  11. We leave it as an exercise for the reader to confirm that both the model in Fig. 2 and the time-indexed model preferred by Halpern and Pearl contain vulnerable arcs.

  12. It might be wondered why anything needs to be done more than simply setting C to its actual value. This will then get the result, however, on most analyses, that Suzy’s throw is not a cause of the bottle smashing. See Korb et al. (2005) for further discussion of a strategy to proceed beyond a wounded model to a complete analysis.

  13. Note that our account does not, on its own, explain the tendency to rule Suzy as a cause more often for some backups than others. For instance, if the backup is a human, rather than a brick wall, it is more common to judge that Suzy is a cause. However, strategies that have been suggested by others to explain such phenomena (e.g. Collins’s “dependence prevention” account (2004)), appear to be compatible with our preferred approach.

References

  • Collins, J. (2004). Preëmptive prevention. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 107–117). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowe, P. (2000). Physical causation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fair, D. (1979). Causation and the flow of energy. Erkenntnis, 14, 219–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, N. (2004). Two concepts of causation. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 225–276). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halpern, J. Y., & Pearl, J. (2005). Causes and explanations: A structural–model approach. Part I: causes. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 56, 843–887.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hiddleston, E. (2005). Causal powers. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 56, 27–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C. (2001). The intransitivity of causation revealed in equations and graphs. Journal of Philosophy, 98(6), 273–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korb, K. B., Twardy, C. R., Handfield, T., & Oppy, G. (2005). Causal reasoning with causal models. Technical Report 2005/183, Monash University, Faculty of Information Technology.

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Causation. Journal of Philosophy, 70, 556–567. Reprinted (plus postscripts) in his Philosophical Papers (Vol. 2, pp. 159–240). Oxford: Oxford University Press (1986).

  • Lewis, D. (2000). Causation as influence. Journal of Philosophy, 97, 182–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (2004). Void and object. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 277–290). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDermott, M. (1995). Redundant causation. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46, 523–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menzies, P. (1999). Intrinsic versus extrinsic conceptions of causation. In H. Sankey (Ed.), Causation and laws of nature (pp. 313–329). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menzies, P. (2004a). Causal models, token causation, and processes. Philosophy of Science, 71, 820–832.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menzies, P. (2004b). Difference making in context. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals. (pp. 139–180). Cambridge, MA.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Molnar, G. (2000). Truthmakers for negative truths. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 78, 72–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. A. W. (1972). The philosophy of logical atomism. In D. Pears (Ed.), Russell’s logical atomism. London: Collins. First published 1918.

  • Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2001). Causation, influence, and effluence. Analysis, 61, 11–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1922). Tractatus logico-philosophicus. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Translated by C. K. Ogden.

  • Woodward, J., & Hitchcock, C. (2003). Explanatory generalizations, part I: A counterfactual account. Noûs, 37, 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This research was supported by a Monash University Arts–IT Grant. Handfield’s work on this paper was supported, in part, by a Monash University Research Fund Postdoctoral Fellowship and, in part, by an Australian Research Council APD Fellowship. Thanks for helpful comments or suggestions to two anonymous referees and to audiences at Oxford and at the Australasian Association of Philosophy Conference, Sydney, 2005.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Toby Handfield.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Handfield, T., Twardy, C.R., Korb, K.B. et al. The Metaphysics of Causal Models. Erkenn 68, 149–168 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-007-9060-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-007-9060-3

Keywords

Navigation