skip to main content
article

Minds, Machines and Turing

Authors Info & Claims
Published:01 October 2000Publication History
Skip Abstract Section

Abstract

Turing's celebrated 1950 paper proposes a very general methodological criterion for modelling mental function: total functional equivalence and indistinguishability. His criterion gives rise to a hierarchy of Turing Tests, from subtotal (“toy”) fragments of our functions (t1), to total symbolic (pen-pal) function (T2 – the standard Turing Test), to total external sensorimotor (robotic) function (T3), to total internal microfunction (T4), to total indistinguishability in every empirically discernible respect (T5). This is a “reverse-engineering’ hierarchy of (decreasing) empirical underdetermination of the theory by the data. Level t1 is clearly too underdetermined, T2 is vulnerable to a counterexample (Searle's Chinese Room Argument), and T4 and T5 are arbitrarily overdetermined. Hence T3 is the appropriate target level for cognitive science. When it is reached, however, there will still remain more unanswerable questions than when Physics reaches its Grand Unified Theory of Everything (GUTE), because of the mind/body problem and the other-minds problem, both of which are inherent in this empirical domain, even though Turing hardly mentions them.

References

  1. Alcock, J.E., 1987, "Parapsychology: Science of the anomalous or search for the soul?," Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10, 553-565.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  2. Black, M., 1952, "The identity of indiscernibles," Mind 61, 152-164.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  3. Crockett, L., 1994, The Turing Test and the Frame Problem: AI's Mistaken Understanding of Intelligence, Norwood, NJ: Ablex. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  4. Davidson, D., 1990, "Turing's Test," pp. 1-11 in Modelling the Mind, K.A. Mohyeldin Said, W.H. Newton-Smith, R. Viale, and K.V. Wilkes, eds., Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  5. Dennett, D., 1985, "Can machines think?," in How We Know, M. Shafto, ed., San Francisco, CA: Harper & Row.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  6. Dennett, D.C., 1994, "Cognitive science as reverse engineering," pp. 679-689 in Proceedings of the 9th International Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, D. Prawitz, B. Skyrms, and D. Westerstahl, eds., Amsterdam: North-Holland.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  7. Dennett, D.C. and Kinsbourne, M., 1995, "Time and the observer: The where and when of consciousness in the brain," Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15, 183-247.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  8. French, R., 1990, "Subcognition and the limits of the Turing Test," Mind 99, 53-65.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  9. Hadamard, J., 1949, An Essay on the Psychology of Invention in the Mathematical Field, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  10. Harnad, S., 1982a, "Neoconstructivism: A unifying theme for the cognitive sciences," pp. 1-11 in Language, Mind and Brain, T. Simon and R. Scholes, eds., Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  11. Harnad, S., 1982b, "Consciousness: An afterthought," Cognition and Brain Theory 5, 29-47.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  12. Harnad, S., 1984, "Verifying machines' minds (Review of J.T. Culbertson, Consciousness: Natural and artificial, NY: Libra 1982)," Contemporary Psychology 29, 389-391.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  13. Harnad, S., 1985, "Bugs, slugs, computers and consciousness," American Psychologist 73, 21.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  14. Harnad, S., 1989, "Minds, machines and Searle," Journal of Theoretical and Experimental Artificial Intelligence 1, 5-25. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  15. Harnad, S., 1990a, "The symbol grounding problem," Physica D 42, 335-346. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  16. Harnad, S., 1990b, "Against computational hermeneutics (Invited Commentary on Eric Dietrich's Computationalism)," Social Epistemology 4, 167-172.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  17. Harnad, S., 1990c, "Lost in the hermeneutic hall of mirrors. Invited Commentary on: Michael Dyer: Minds, Machines, Searle and Harnad," Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence 2, 321-327. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  18. Harnad, S., 1991, "Other bodies, other minds: A machine incarnation of an old philosophical problem," Minds and Machines 1, 43-54. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  19. Harnad, S., 1992a, "Connecting object to symbol in modeling cognition," pp. 75-90 in Connectionism in Context, A. Clark and R. Lutz, eds., Berlin: Springer-Verlag.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  20. Harnad, S., 1992b, "The Turing test is not a trick: Turing indistinguishability is a scientific criterion," SIGART Bulletin 3 9-10. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  21. Harnad, S., 1993a, "Grounding symbols in the analog world with neural nets," Think 2, 12-78 (Special issue on "Connectionism versus Symbolism," D.M.W. Powers and P.A. Flach, eds.).Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  22. Harnad, S., 1993b, "Artificial life: Synthetic versus virtual," pp. 539-549 in Artificial Life III, Proceedings , C. Langton, ed., Santa Fe Institute Studies in the Sciences of Complexity, Vol. XVI, Reading, MA: Addison Wesley.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  23. Harnad S., 1993c, "Discussion (passim)," in Experimental and Theoretical Studies of Consciousness, G.R. Bock and J. Marsh, eds., CIBA Foundation Symposium 174, Chichester: Wiley.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  24. Harnad, S., 1994a, "Levels of functional equivalence in reverse bioengineering: The Darwinian Turing test for artificial life," Artificial Life 1, 293-301. Reprinted in C.G. Langton, ed., 1995, Artificial Life: An Overview, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  25. Harnad, S., 1994b, "Computation is just interpretable symbol manipulation: Cognition isn't," Minds and Machines 4, 379-390 (Special Issue on "What Is Computation").Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  26. Harnad, S., 1995a, Does the mind piggy-back on robotic and symbolic capacity?," pp. 204-220 in The Mind, the Brain, and Complex Adaptive Systems, H. Morowitz, ed., Santa Fe Institute Studies in the Sciences of Complexity, Vol. XXII, Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  27. Harnad, S., 1995b, "Why and how we are not zombies," Journal of Consciousness Studies 1, 164- 167.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  28. Harnad, S., 1996, "The origin of words: A psychophysical hypothesis," pp. 27-44 in Communicating Meaning: Evolution and Development of Language, B. Velichkovsky and D. Rumbaugh, eds., Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  29. Harnad, S., 2000a, "Turing indistinguishability and the blind watchmaker," in Evolving Consciousness , G. Mulhauser, ed., Amsterdam: John Benjamins (in press).Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  30. Harnad, S., 2000b, "What's wrong and right about Searle's Chinese Room argument?," in Essays on Searle's Chinese Room Argument, M. Bishop and J. Preston, eds., Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  31. Harnad, S., 2000c, "Correlation vs. causality: How/why the mind/body problem is hard," Journal of Consciousness Studies 7, 54-61.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  32. Harnad, S., Doty, R.W., Goldstein, L., Jaynes, J., and Krauthamer, G., eds., 1977, Lateralization in the Nervous System, New York: Academic Press.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  33. Hauser, L., 1993, "Reaping the whirlwind: Reply to Harnad's 'Other bodies, other minds'," Minds and Machines 3, 219-237.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  34. Hayes, P., Harnad, S., Perlis, D., and Block, N., 1992, "Virtual symposium on virtual mind," Minds and Machines 2, 217-238.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  35. Heyes, C.M., 1998, "Theory of mind in nonhuman primates," Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21, 101-134.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  36. Loebner, H.G., 1994, "Lessons from a restricted turing test - In response," Communications of the ACM 37(6), 79-82. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  37. Mitchell, R.W. and Anderson, J.R., 1998, "Primate theory of mind is a Turing test," Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21, 127-128.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  38. Nagel, T., 1974, "What is it like to be a bat?," Philosophical Review 83, 435-451.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  39. Newell, A., 1980, "Physical symbol systems," Cognitive Science 4, 135-183.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  40. Pylyshyn, Z.W., 1980, "Computation and cognition: Issues in the foundations of cognitive science," Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3, 111-169.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  41. Pylyshyn, Z.W., 1984, Computation and Cognition, Cambridge, MA: MIT/Bradford.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  42. Pylyshyn, Z.W., ed., 1987, The Robot's Dilemma: The Frame Problem in Artificial Intelligence, Norwood NJ: Ablex. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  43. Schweizer, P., 1998, "The truly total Turing test," Minds and Machines 8, 263-272. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  44. Searle, J.R., 1980, "Minds, brains, and programs," Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3, 417-457.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  45. Searle, J.R., 1984, Minds, Brains and Science, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  46. Searle, J.R., 1990, "Consciousness, explanatory inversion, and cognitive science," Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13, 585-642.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  47. Searle, J.R., 1993, "The failures of computationalism," THINK 2, 70-77.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  48. Shieber, S.M., 1994, "Lessons from a restricted Turing test," Communications of the ACM 37, 70-78. Google ScholarGoogle ScholarDigital LibraryDigital Library
  49. Steklis, H.D. and Harnad, S., 1976, "From hand to mouth: Some critical stages in the evolution of language," pp. 445-455 in Origins and Evolution of Language and Speech, S. Harnad, H.D. Steklis, and J.B. Lancaster, eds., Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, Vol. 280, New York: New York Academy of Sciences.Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  50. Turing, A.M., 1950, "Computing machinery and intelligence," Mind 49, 433-460. (Reprinted in A. Anderson, ed., 1964, Minds and Machines, Engelwood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.)Google ScholarGoogle ScholarCross RefCross Ref
  51. Watt, S., 1996, "Naive psychology and the inverted Turing test," PSYCOLOQUY 7.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar
  52. Wimsatt, W.K., 1954, The Verbal Icon: Studies in the Meaning of Poetry, Louisville: University Press of Kentucky.Google ScholarGoogle Scholar

Recommendations

Comments

Login options

Check if you have access through your login credentials or your institution to get full access on this article.

Sign in

Full Access