Skip to main content
Log in

Dreyfus and Haugeland on Heidegger and Authenticity

  • Theoretical / Philosophical Paper
  • Published:
Human Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper tries to read some structure into the perplexing diversity of the literature on Heidegger’s concept of authenticity. It argues that many of the interpretations available rely on views that are false and cannot be Heidegger’s. It also shows that the only correct interpretation of Heidegger’s concept of authenticity emerges from a synthesis of Dreyfus’ later interpretation and Haugeland’s interpretation of this concept. A synthesis of these interpretations yields an interpretation, according to which Dasein’s being is authentic only if it is capable of using tools or language in radically new ways.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It is questionable whether the customary translation of the German Eigentlichkeit by the English ‘authenticity’ is fortunate. In what follows, however, I shall not elaborate on the questionability of this translation and will simply maintain the use of the term ‘authenticity’.

  2. See my “Heidegger on Authenticity” (forthcoming). Both my “Heidegger on Authenticity” and the present paper arrive at similar conclusions but go different ways to establish these conclusions. My “Heidegger on Authenticity” concludes that Heidegger’s concept of authenticity is best interpreted in terms of the concept of originality and derives this conclusion by providing a textual analysis of central passages of Being and Time and related texts. The present paper, by contrast, concludes that an adequate interpretation of Heidegger’s concept of authenticity emerges from a synthesis of Dreyfus’ later interpretation and Haugeland’s interpretation of this concept and attempts to establish this conclusion with the aid of a discussion of existing interpretations of this concept (and especially the ones brought forward by Dreyfus and Haugeland).

  3. Carman criticizes early Dreyfus’ interpretation in Carman (2000) and Guignon’s interpretation in Carman 2000: 271–273. Later Dreyfus criticizes early Dreyfus’ interpretation in Dreyfus (2000). Individual criticisms of all five interpretations can be found in my Henschen (2010).

  4. This view was probably first articulated by Tugendhat (1966: 309) and then adopted by Figal (1988: 260–261, 303–304).

  5. Guignon himself acknowledges that his interpretation of authenticity is in conflict with this thesis. He states that his interpretation runs “counter to the awareness of wordliness and thrownness that is central to Being and Time” (Guignon 2000: 91). But instead of giving up on this interpretation, he believes the project of Being and Time to be defective in that it grounds “all ontology in something like the total transparency of self to self” (Guignon 2000: 91). It is well known that Heidegger himself regarded his project of Being and Time to be defective in a number of ways: one is with respect to its alleged anthropocentrism (cf. B 300f.), another is with respect to its concept of truth (cf. EPTT 446). It is questionable, however, whether it can be interpreted as being defective in the way envisaged by Guignon.

  6. He suggests, for instance, that someone directs himself by a signpost “only in so far as there exists a regular use of signposts, a custom” (PI §198). He also repeatedly emphasizes the importance of training, drill and exercises in inculcating techniques within groups of people (PI §§189, 208). He, finally, explicitly mentions the social character of a language: the very possibility of a language, he says, rests on an agreement among speakers in definitions and judgements (PI §242).

  7. As is well known from Baker and Hacker (1984), Baker and Hacker are quite critical of Kripke’s interpretation of Wittgenstein. But even according to Kripke’s interpretation, we cannot say that Wittgenstein believed in the necessary publicness of understanding. Like Baker and Hacker Kripke examines the case of physically isolated individuals like Robinson Crusoe. The dire situation of this particular individual can easily be thought of as leading it to invent new ways of using tools or language to hunt or name species that had been unknown before. But when inventing new ways of using tools or language, Crusoe obviously introduces new rules of using tools or language. Accordingly, Kripke’s conclusion is not that he does not follow any rules when using tools or language in this newly invented way: “Does this mean that Robinson Crusoe, isolated on an island, cannot be said to follow any rules, no matter what he does? I do not see that this follows” (Kripke 1982: 110). What Kripke’s conclusion states is that Crusoe cannot be said to be able to justify his belief (i.e. to know) that he follows any rules when using tools or language in a newly invented way. He cannot justify this belief unless he is included in some sort of community and able to teach his newly invented ways of using tools or language to other people who may then set up criteria for rule following which enable them to judge whether someone follows a rule or not: “What does follow is that if we think of Crusoe as following rules, we are taking him into our community and applying our criteria for rule following to him” (Kripke 1982: 110). Kripke also points out that the fact that physically isolated individuals do not know whether they follow any rules is no reason to panic:“[C]onsider what is true of one person considered in isolation. The most obvious fact is one that might have escaped us after long contemplation of the sceptical paradox. It holds no terrors in our daily lives; no one actually hesitates when asked to produce an answer to an addition problem! […] The entire point of the sceptical argument is that ultimately we reach a level where we act without any reason in terms of which we can justify our action. We act unhesitatingly but blindly” (Kripke 1982: 87).

  8. For a detailed justification of this claim see my Henschen (2010: especially 96–97).

  9. A similar interpretation can already be found in Dreyfus (1991: 208ff).

  10. See my “Heidegger on Authenticity” (forthcoming).

References

  • Baker, G. P., & Hacker, P. M. S. (1984). Scepticism, rules, and language. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, G. P., & Hacker, P. M. S. (1985). Rules, Grammar, and Necessity. An analytical commentary on the Philosophical investigations, vol. 2. Oxford: Blackwell, 41997.

  • Brandom, R. (1983). Heidegger’s categories in ‘being and time’. Monist, 66, 387–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carman, T. (2000). Must We be inauthentic? In: Heidegger, authenticity, and modernity: essays in Honor of Hubert L. Dreyfus, Vol. I. Hrsg. v. J. Malpas u. M. A. Wrathall. Cambridge, MIT Press, pp 13–28.

  • Carman, T. (2003). Heidegger’s analytic. Cambridge, MA: CUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carman, T. (2005). Authenticity. In: A companion to heidegger. Hrsg. v. H. L. Dreyfus u. M. A. Wrathall. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing Ltd., pp. 285–296.

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (1991). Being-in-the-World. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2000a). Could anything be more intelligible than everyday intelligibility? Reinterpreting division I of ‘being and time’ in the light of division II. In M. A. Wrathall & J. Faulconer (Eds.), Appropriating Heidegger (pp. 155–174). Cambridge, MA: CUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2000b). Response to Haugeland. In J. Malpas & M. A. Wrathall (Eds.), Heidegger, authenticity, and modernity: essays in honor of Hubert L. Dreyfus (Vol. I, pp. 312–319). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2005). Overcoming the myth of the mental. In: Proceedings and addresses of the American Philosophical Association, vol. 79, no. 2, pp. 47–65.

  • Figal, G. (1988). Martin Heidegger. Phänomenologie der Freiheit. Frankfurt a. M.: Athenäum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guignon, C. (2000). Philosophy and authenticity Heidegger’s search for a ground for Philosophizing. In J. Malpas & M. A. Wrathall (Eds.), Heidegger, authenticity, and modernity: essays in honor of Hubert L. Dreyfus (Vol. I, pp. 79–102). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J. (2000). Truth and finitude: Heidegger’s transcendental existentialism. In J. Malpas & M. A. Wrathall (Eds.), Heidegger, authenticity, and modernity: essays in honor of Hubert L. Dreyfus (Vol. I, pp. 43–78). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1922). Phenomenological interpretations with respect to Aristotle: indication of the hermeneutical situation. In Man and World (trans: Baur M). pp. 355–393 (cited as PIRA).

  • Heidegger, M. (1925). History of the Concept of Time (trans: Kisiel T). Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1985 (cited as HCT).

  • Heidegger, M. (1927). Being and Time (trans: Macquarrie, J., & Robinson, E.). New York: Harper-Collins, 1962 (cited as BT).

  • Heidegger, M. (1939). Beiträge zur Philosophie (vom Ereignis). Herrmann. Frankfurt/Main: Klostermann, 32003 (cited as B).

  • Heidegger, M. (1962). On Time and Being (trans: Stambaugh J). Harper & Row: New York (cited as TB).

  • Heidegger, M. (1964). The end of philosophy and the task of thinking. In Krell, D. F (Ed.), Basic Writings. Harper Collins: New York 1993 (cited as EPTT).

  • Heidegger, Martin. (1935/36). What is a Thing? (trans: Barton, W. B., Jr, Deutsch, V). South Bend, Indiana: Regnery/Gateway, 1967 (cited as WT).

  • Henschen, T. (2010). Gebrauch oder Herstellung? Heidegger über Eigentlichkeit, Wahrheit und phänomenologische Methode. Paderborn: Mentis.

  • Kripke, S. A. (1982). Wittgenstein on rules and private language (p. 112002). Cambridge, MA: HUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okrent, M. (1988). Heidegger’s pragmatism. Understanding, being, and the critique of metaphysics. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olafson, F. A. (1994). Heidegger à la Wittgenstein or ‘coping’ with Professor Dreyfus. Inquiry, 37, 45–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tugendhat E (1966). Heideggers Idee von Wahrheit. In Heidegger. Hrsg. v. O. Pöggeler. Köln/Berlin: Kiepenheuer & Witsch.

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1945). Philosophische Untersuchungen. Werkausgabe Band 1. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp, 101995 (cited as: PI).

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tobias Henschen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Henschen, T. Dreyfus and Haugeland on Heidegger and Authenticity. Hum Stud 35, 95–113 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-012-9212-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-012-9212-6

Keywords

Navigation