Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Mirroring versus simulation: on the representational function of simulation

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Mirror neurons and systems are often appealed to as mechanisms enabling mindreading, i.e., understanding other people’s mental states. Such neural mirroring processes are often treated as instances of mental simulation rather than folk psychological theorizing. I will call into question this assumed connection between mirroring and simulation, arguing that mirroring does not necessarily constitute mental simulation as specified by the simulation theory of mindreading. I begin by more precisely characterizing “mirroring” (Sect. 2) and “simulation” (Sect. 3). Mirroring results in a neural process in an observer that resembles a neural process of the same type in the observed agent. Although simulation is often characterized in terms of resemblance (Goldman, Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mindreading, 2006), I argue that simulation requires more than mere interpersonal mental resemblance: A simulation must have the purpose or function of resembling its target (Sect. 3.1). Given that mirroring processes are generated automatically, I focus on what is required for a simulation to possess the function of resembling its target. In Sect. 3.2 I argue that this resemblance function, at least in the case of simulation-based mindreading, requires that a simulation serve as a representation or stand-in of what it resembles. With this revised account of simulation in hand, in Sect. 4 I show that the mirroring processes do not necessarily possess the representational function required of simulation. To do so I describe an account of goal attribution involving a motor mirroring process that should not be characterized as interpersonal mental simulation. I end in Sect. 5 by defending the conceptual distinction between mirroring and simulation, and discussing the implications of this argument for the kind of neuroscientific evidence required by simulation theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Anderson M. L. (2010) Neural re-use as a fundamental organizational principle of the brain. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33: 245–313

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bergeron V. (2007) Anatomical and functional modularity in cognitive science: Shifting the focus. Philosophical Psychology 20(2): 175–195

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biggs S. (2007) The phenomenal mindreader: A case for phenomenal simulation. Philosophical Psychology 20(1): 29–42

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biggs S. (2009) Phenomenal concepts in mindreading. Philosophical Psychology 22(6): 647–667

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore S.-J., Decety J. (2001) From perception of action to the understanding of intention. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 2: 561–567

    Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore S.-J., Frith C. (2005) The role of motor contagion in the prediction of action. Neuropsychologia 43: 260–267

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins R. (1996) Representations, targets and attitudes. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Csibra G. (2007) Action mirroring and action interpretation: An alternative account. In: Haggard P., Rosetti Y., Kawato M. (eds) Sensorimotor foundations of higher cognition. Attention and performance XXII. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 427–451

    Google Scholar 

  • di Pellegrino G., Fadiga L., Fogassi L., Gallese V., Rizzolatti G. (1992) Understanding motor events: A neurophysiological study. Experimental Brain Research 91(1): 176–180

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Etzel J. A., Gazzola V., Keysers C. (2008) Testing simulation theory with cross-modal multivariate classification of fMRI data. PLoS one 3(11): e3690

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher J. (2006) Does simulation theory really involve simulation?. Philosophical Psychology 19(4): 417–432

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fogassi L., Ferrari P. F., Gesierich B., Rozzi S., Chersi F., Rizzolatti G. (2005) Parietal lobe: From action organization to intention understanding. Science 308: 662–667

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese V. (2001) The “shared manifold” hypothesis. Journal of Consciousness Studies 8(5–7): 33–50

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese V., Fadiga L., Fogassi L., Rizzolatti G. (1996) Action recognition in the premotor cortex. Brain 119: 593–609

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese V., Goldman A. (1998) Mirror neurons and the simulation theory of mind-reading. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 2(12): 493–501

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese V., Keysers C., Rizzolatti G. (2004) A unifying view of the basis of social cognition. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 8(9): 396–403

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gazzola V., Keysers C. (2009) The observation and execution of actions share motor and somatosensory voxels in all tested subjects: Single-subject analyses of unsmoothed fMRI data. Cerebral Cortex 19(6): 1239–1255

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (2005, January 25). Reply to Csibra. Discussion of “Mirror systems, social understanding and social cognition.” Interdisciplines: What do mirror neurons mean? Retrieved March 14, 2011, from http://www.interdisciplines.org/medias/confs/archives/archive_8.pdf.

  • Goldman A. I. (2006) Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mindreading. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman A. I. (2009a) Mirroring, mindreading, and simulation. In: Pineda J. A. (Ed.) Mirror neuron systems. Humana Press, New York, pp 311–330

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman A. I. (2009b) Mirroring, simulating and mindreading. Mind and Language 24(2): 235–252

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman A. I. (2009c) Simulation theory and cognitive neuroscience. In: Murphy D., Bishop M. (eds) Stich and his critics. Wiley/Blackwell, Malden, MA, pp 137–151

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I., & Shanton, K. (in press). The case for simulation theory. In A. Leslie & T. German (Eds.), Handbook of “Theory of mind.”. New York: Psychology Press.

  • Gordon R. (2008) Beyond mindreading. Philosophical Explorations 11(3): 219–222

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grush R. (1997) The architecture of representation. Philosophical Psychology 10(1): 5–23

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley S. (2008) The shared circuits model: How control, mirroring, and simulation can enable imitation, deliberation, and mindreading. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31: 1–58

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Iacoboni M. (2008) Mirroring people: The new science of how we connect with others. Farrar Straus and Giroux, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Iacoboni M., Molnar-Szackas I., Gallese V., Buccino G., Mazziotta J. C., Rizzolatti G. (2005) Grasping the intentions of others with one’s own mirror neuron system. PLoS Biology 3(79): 529–535

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson P., Meltzoff A., Decety J. (2005) How do we perceive the pain of others? A window into the neural processes involved in empathy. NeuroImage 24: 771–779

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacob P. (2009a) The tuning-fork model of human social cognition: A critique. Consciousness and Cognition 18: 229–243

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacob P. (2009b) What do mirror neurons contribute to human social cognition?. Mind & Language 23(2): 190–223

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keysers C., Gazzola V. (2009a) Expanding the mirror: Vicarious activity for actions, emotions, and sensations. Current Opinion in Neurobiology 19: 666–671

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keysers C., Gazzola V. (2009b) Unifying social cognition. In: Pineda J. A. (Ed.) Mirror neuron systems. Humana Press, New York, pp 3–37

    Google Scholar 

  • Kilner J. M., Friston K. J., Frith C. D. (2007a) The mirror-neuron system: A Bayesian perspective. NeuroReport 18(6): 619–623

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kilner J. M., Friston K. J., Frith C. D. (2007b) Predictive coding: An account of the mirror neuron system. Cognitive Processing 8: 159–166

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan R. G. (1989) Biosemantics. Journal of Philosophy 86(6): 281–297

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mukamel R., Ekstrom A., Kaplan J., Iacoboni M., Fried I. (2010) Single-neuron responses in humans during execution and observation of actions. Current Biology 20: 750–756

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oberman L. M., Ramachandran V. S. (2007) The simulating social mind: The role of the mirror neuron system and simulation in the social and communicative deficits of autism spectrum disorders. Psychological Bulletin 133(2): 310–327

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien G., Opie J. (2004) Notes toward a structuralist theory of mental representation. In: Clapin H., Staines P., Slezak P. (eds) Representation in mind: New approaches to mental representation. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 1–20

    Google Scholar 

  • Oztop E., Wolpert D., Kawato M. (2005) Mental state inference using visual control parameters. Brain Research Cognitive Brain Research 22(2): 129–151

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palmer S. E. (1978) Fundamental aspects of cognitive representation. In: Rosch E., Lloyd B. B. (eds) Cognition and categorization. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Hillsdale, NJ, pp 259–303

    Google Scholar 

  • Pineda J. A. (2009) Action mirroring and action interpretation: An alternative account. In: Pineda J. A. (Ed.) Mirror neuron systems: The role of mirroring processes in social cognition. Humana, New York, pp 5–8

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey W. (2007) Representation reconsidered. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey W. (2010) How not to build a hybrid: Simulation vs. fact-finding. Philosophical Psychology 23(6): 775–795

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti G., Craighero L. (2004) The mirror-neuron system. Annual Review of Neuroscience 27: 169–192

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti G., Fadiga L., Gallese V., Fogassi L. (1996) Premotor cortex and the recognition of motor actions. Cognitive Brain Research 3: 131–141

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti G., Fogassi L., Gallese V. (2001) Neurophysiological mechanisms underlying the understanding and imitation of action. Nature Review Neuroscience 2: 661–670

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti G., Fogassi L., Gallese V. (2004) Cortical mechanisms subserving object grasping, action understanding, and imitation. In: Gazzaniga M. (Ed.) The cognitive neurosciences III. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 427–440

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti G., Sinigaglia C. (2008) Mirrors in the brain: How our minds share actions and emotions. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti G., Sinigaglia C. (2010) The functional role of the parieto-frontal mirror circuit: Interpretations and misinterpretations. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 11(4): 264–274

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shanton K., Goldman A. (2010) Simulation theory. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science 1(4): 527–538

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepard R. N., Chipman S. (1970) Second-order isomorphism of internal representations: Shapes of states. Cognitive Psychology 1: 1–17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer T., Seymour B., O’Doherty J., Kaube H., Dolan R., Frith C. (2004) Empathy for pain involves affective but not sensory components of pain. Science 303: 1157–1162

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stich S., Nichols S. (1997) Cognitive penetrability, rationality, and restricted simulation. Mind and Language 12: 297–326

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uithol, S., van Rooij, I., Bekkering, H., & Haselager, P. (in press). Understanding motor resonance. Social neuroscience.

  • Von Eckardt B. (1993) What is cognitive science?. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Waskan J. (2006) Models and cognition. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Wicker B., Keysers C., Plailly J., Royet J.-P., Gallese G., Rizzolatti V. (2003) Both of us disgusted in my insula: The common neural basis of seeing and feeling disgust. Neuron 40: 655–664

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mitchell Herschbach.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Herschbach, M. Mirroring versus simulation: on the representational function of simulation. Synthese 189, 483–513 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-011-9969-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-011-9969-6

Keywords

Navigation