Skip to main content
Log in

On being stuck in time

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is sometimes claimed that non-human animals (and perhaps also young children) live their lives entirely in the present and are cognitively ‘stuck in time’. Adult humans, by contrast, are said to be able to engage in ‘mental time travel’. One possible way of making sense of this distinction is in terms of the idea that animals and young children cannot engage in tensed thought, which might seem a preposterous idea in the light of certain findings in comparative and developmental psychology. I try to make this idea less preposterous by looking into some of the cognitive requirements for tensed thought. In particular, I suggest that tensed thought requires a specific form of causal understanding, which animals and young children may not possess.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Davidson (1982) is an obvious contemporary example.

  2. For some other versions of this claim, or at least similar claims, made at various points in the history of philosophy see, e.g., Aristotle (1930, 453a4–13), Schopenhauer (1999, p. 30), Bergson (1988, pp. 93f.), Dennett (2005, pp. 168f.). In psychology, influential sources for the claim that animals’ cognitive life is restricted to the present include Koehler (1927, p. 272) and (as one referee has pointed out to me) Donald (1991, p. 149). Of course, it is not necessary to see this claim as being in competition with the claim that the deep discontinuity between humans and other animals turns on the fact that the latter lack language. Bennett (1964), whom I will discuss below, is one example of a philosopher who thinks that the two claims are connected.

  3. The experimenters actually removed the cached items before testing to ensure that the birds were not able to base their searches on olfactory cues. There was also a control involving scrub jays that were not given the training trial, but then went through the same test phase.

  4. See, e.g. Zentall (2005), see also Hoerl (2001), for a similar point.

  5. Of course, the former type of notion may also be seen as employing tense, i.e. the present tense. I will shortly try to make a case for saying that the crucial distinction at issue here is indeed one between notions that employ tense and notions that do not employ tense at all, even though we might have to use present tense morphology to capture the latter in English.

  6. I am simplifying the dialectical situation here. Bennett (1976), from which the first quotation in this paragraph is taken, actually goes on to criticise the argument from Bennett (1964) that I have sketched. He suggests that non-linguistic behaviour might, after all, warrant the ascription of separate past and general beliefs, if there is a range of different behaviours the animal engages in that can be explained by attributing a past belief that combines with a number of different general beliefs or vice versa. Smith’s (1982) paper, from which the second quotation is taken, considers this suggestion and argues that it underestimates the strength of Bennett’s (1964) argument, i.e. the undercutting strategy can be made to work even in cases where there is a range of behaviours as envisaged by Bennett (1976). For the purposes of this paper, I will assume that Smith’s defense of Bennett’s (1964) argument is sound.

  7. See also the discussion of Campbell’s (2006) views below.

  8. On some accounts of propositional attitudes, we should actually hold back from crediting the dog with beliefs at all if the argument offered here is correct. Elsewhere in this paper, I also speak of animals’ (and childrens’) ‘model of the world’, which is perhaps a more neutral expression.

  9. This is not to say that this is the only cognitive role timing mechanisms can play. Peacocke (1999), for instance, develops an account according to which a sensitivity to temporal relations, mediated by such mechanisms, does in fact also have a crucial role to play in understanding the past tense. However, he also notes that “[t]o possess a sub-personal mechanism which is, when functioning properly, [...] temporally sensitive is of course not yet to have mastered temporal thought” (Peacocke 1999, p. 90), which is in effect the same issue that is at stake in the above quotation from McCormack (2001).

  10. There are also cases in which it might be more appropriate to say that the function of the timing mechanism is to suppress certain elements of the model for periods of time. This type of description might be applied, for instance, to capture the role interval timers have in preventing hummingbirds from revisiting a food source for a certain period of time, thus allowing the food source to replenish (cf. Henderson et al. 2006). I should also add, here, that we need to allow that the model an animal operates with might be fairly disunified, or, as we might also put it, that an animal might be seen to operate with several different models, which are updated in different ways and on different timescales, relative to different sets of practical purposes. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for alerting me to this latter point.

  11. A similar thought is fleshed out further in McCormack and Hoerl (1999), who relate research on children’s acquisition of scripts to a view in linguistics according to which aspectual notions (e.g., completed, ongoing...) are grasped before tensed ones (e.g., past, present...) (see Wagner 2001, for a recent discussion). McCormack and Hoerl (1999) suggest that children’s recounting or re-enacting scripts might indicate an ability to mark events successively as, e.g., ongoing vs. completed, as they go through the script. This ability appears to be more primitive than a grasp of tenses, though, in that it need not involve use of the notion of the time at which an event happens. A child might first think of an event as ongoing, and then as completed, without being able to grasp, say, at the time when she thinks of the event as completed, that there was a time when it was ongoing. In contrast, thinking of an event as past, say, arguably involves assigning it a position in a domain of times, as is also brought out by the quotation from Campbell (2006) above.

  12. Both types of imagination mentioned here might require the ability to set aside current desires or other mental states in imagination. The development of this ability is explored in experiments carried out, e.g. by Atance and Meltzoff (2006) and by Suddendorf and Busby (2005), which claim to investigate the development of mental time travelling in children. However, precisely because that ability might be required for either form of imaginative exercise mentioned above, it should be clear that there is a further aspect of mental time travel that those experiments don’t tap into.

  13. A similar distinction is sometimes drawn in the literature on the development of counterfactual reasoning. It has been argued that some developmental studies might have over-estimated children’s command of counterfactuals, because the correct answer to the counterfactual test question could be arrived at by engaging in purely hypothetical reasoning, whereas children of a similar age fail counterfactual tasks that require ‘thinking back in time’ and considering the particular events that actually happened. See Beck et al. (2006) for discussion.

  14. See also Martin 2001, p. 280, writing about episodic memory: “The infant needs to make sense of how there can be specific, and hence actual, events of which it has [...] conscious awareness, but which are nevertheless not part of the present scene”.

  15. There is in fact a range of the type of ‘temporal-causal’ relationships exemplified by Atance's task, in which an overall outcome depends on the order in which two or more events happen. Children’s understanding of these types of relationships has also been explored, using quite different methodologies in Povinelli et al. (1999) and McCormack and Hoerl (2007). In these studies, children under 4–5 years typically perform quite poorly, indicating a lack of a grasp of the relevant temporal-causal relationships.

References

  • Aristotle (1930). On memory and reminiscence. In W. D. Ross (Ed.) The works of Aristotle (vol. 3). Oxford: Clarendon Press (translated by J. I. Beare; originally written ca. 350).

    Google Scholar 

  • Atance, C. (2006). Contribution to symposium on mental time travel, Annual meeting of the European Society for Philosophy and Psychology, Belfast, August 2006.

  • Atance, C. M., & Meltzoff, A. N. (2006). Preschoolers’ current desires warp their choices for the future. Psychological Science, 17, 583–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beck, S. R., Robinson, E. J., Carroll, D. J., & Apperly, I. A. (2006). Children’s thinking about counterfactuals and future hypotheticals as possibilities. Child Development, 77, 413–426.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, J. (1964). Rationality: an essay towards an analysis. London, U.K.: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, J. (1976). Linguistic behaviour. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, H. (1988). Matter and memory,. Cambridge, MA: Zone Books (trans by N. M. Paul and W. S. Palmer; originally published in 1896).

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (2006). Ordinary thinking about time. In F. Stadler, & M. Stoeltzner (Eds.) Time and history: Proceedings of the 28th international Wittgenstein symposium 2005. Frankfurt: Ontos verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, N. S., & Dickinson, A. (1998). Episodic-like memory during cache recovery by Scrub-jays. Nature, 395, 272–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, N. S., Bussey, T. J., Emery, N. J., & Dickinson, A. (2003). Prometheus to Proust: the case for behavioural criteria for ‘mental time travel’. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7, 436–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1982). Rational animals. Dialectica, 36, 317–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Kort, S. R., Dickinson, A., & Clayton, N. S. (2005). Retrospective cognition by food-caching western scrub-jays. Learning and Motivation, 36, 159–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2005). Sweet dreams: Philosophical obstacles to a science of consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donald, M. (1991). Origins of the modern mind: Three stages in the evolution of culture and cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eichenbaum, H., Fortin, N. J., Ergorul, C., Wright, S. P., & Agster, K. L. (2005). Episodic recollection in animals: “If it walks like a duck and quacks like a duck...”. Learning and Motivation, 36, 190–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, D. P., Dickinson, A., & Clayton, N. S. (1999). Declarative and episodic memory: what can animals remember about their past? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 3, 74–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henderson, J., Hurly, T. A., Bateson, M., & Healy, S. D. (2006). Timing in free-living rufous hummingbirds Selasphorus rufus. Current Biology, 16, 512–515.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoerl, C. (2001). The phenomenology of episodic recall. In C. Hoerl, & T. McCormack (Eds.) Time and memory: Issues in philosophy and psychology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koehler, W. (1927). The mentality of apes. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul (translated by E. Winter, originally published 1917).

    Google Scholar 

  • McCormack, T. (2001). Attributing episodic memory to animals and children. In C. Hoerl, & T. McCormack (Eds.) Time and memory: Issues in philosophy and psychology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCormack, T., & Hoerl, C. (1999). Memory and temporal perspective: The role of temporal frameworks in memory development. Developmental Review, 19, 154–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCormack, T., & Hoerl, C. (2001). The child in time: Temporal concepts and self-consciousness in the development of episodic memory. In C. Moore, & K. Lemmon (Eds.) The self in time: developmental perspectives. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCormack, T., & Hoerl, C. (2007). Young children’s reasoning about the order of past events. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 98, 168–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. (2001). Episodic recall as retained acquaintance. In C. Hoerl, & T. McCormack (Eds.) Time and memory: Issues in philosophy and psychology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. (1983). Untimely meditations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (translated by R.J. Hollingdale, originally published 1876).

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1999). Being Known. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Perner, J., Kloo, D., & Stöttinger, E. (2007). Introspection and remembering. Synthese, 159, 253–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Povinelli, D. J., Landry, A. M., Theall, L. A., Clark, B. R., & Castille, C. M. (1999). Development of young children’s understanding that the recent past is causally bound to the present. Developmental Psychology, 35, 1426–1439.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schopenhauer, A. (1999). Prize essay on the freedom of the will. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (edited by G. Zöller, translated by E.F.J. Payne; originally published 1840).

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, P. (1982). Bennett’s beliefs. Philosophical Studies, 41, 431–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suddendorf, T., & Busby, J. (2003). Mental time travel in animals? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7, 391–369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suddendorf, T., & Busby, J. (2005). Making decisions with the future in mind: developmental and comparative identification of mental time travel. Learning and Motivation, 36, 110–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suddendorf, T., & Corballis, M. C. (1997). Mental time travel and the evolution of the human mind. Genetic, Social, and General Psychology Monographs, 123, 133–167.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suddendorf, T., & Corballis, M. C. (2007). The evolution of foresight: what is mental time travel and is it unique to humans? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30, 299–313.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E. (1972). Episodic and semantic memory. In E. Tulving, & W. Donaldson (Eds.) Organization of memory (pp. 381–403). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E. (2001). Episodic memory and common sense: How far apart? Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 356, 1505–1515.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, L. (2001). Aspectual influences on early tense comprehension. Journal of Child Language, 28, 661–681.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wearden, J. (2001). Internal clocks and the representation of time. In C. Hoerl, & T. McCormack (Eds.) Time and memory: Issues in philosophy and psychology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zentall, T. R. (2005). Animals may not be stuck in time. Learning and Motivation, 36, 208–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zentall, T. R. (2006). Mental time travel in animals: a challenging question. Behavioural Processes, 72, 173–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Many of the lines of thought developed in this paper emerged from discussions I have had over the years with Teresa McCormack. The paper itself started life as my contribution to a symposium on mental time travel that she organized at the 2006 meeting of the European Society for Philosophy and Psychology at Queen’s University Belfast, where the other symposiasts were Cristina Atance and Thomas Zentall. Later versions of the paper were also presented at seminars at Macquarie University, Sydney, and at the Australian National University, Canberra. I am very grateful to the audiences at those different occasions, and to two anonymous referees for this journal, for a variety of helpful comments. Work on this paper took place within the context of the AHRC Project on Causal Understanding.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christoph Hoerl.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Hoerl, C. On being stuck in time. Phenom Cogn Sci 7, 485–500 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-008-9089-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-008-9089-z

Keywords

Navigation