Skip to main content
Log in

Note on Two Snowdon Criticisms of the Causal Theory of Perception

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Two arguments Paul Snowdon has brought against the causal theory of perception are examined. One involves the claim that, based on the phenomenology of perceptual situations, it cannot be the case that perception is an essentially causal concept. The other is a reductio, according to which causal theorists’ arguments imply that a proposition Snowdon takes to be obviously non-causal (A is married to B) can be analyzed into some sort of indefinite ‘spousal connection’ plus a causal ingredient. I conclude that neither argument is sound. The reason that Snowdon’s critiques fail is that, since causal theories need not be about ‘effect ends’ that are internally manifest to perceivers, no such ostensibly separable, non-causal property as it being to S as if he were perceiving O need be an essential element in a causal theory of perception.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Numerous other versions of this definition may be found in Vision 1997. It is noteworthy that Snowdon himself has fluctuated a bit on precisely how to put this definition. In Snowdon 1981:175-176 the “causal thesis” is any claim to the effect that it is necessarily true that if any S sees any public object O, then O causally affects S. But Snowdon takes the whole causal theory to be comprised not only of that thesis, but also to assert (i) that the sort of effect of this causal process is reportable in a “looks-statement;” and (ii) that the other two theses are “conceptual truths.” In Snowdon 1990: 123, these three theses are put into a single proposition, thus arguably defining CTP more restrictively than I have. The definition in that work is, roughly, It is a conceptual requirement that, necessarily, if S perceives O then O is causally responsible for an experience undergone by S. This could be held to be stronger than my definition, which entails only two of the three Snowdon theses, since it makes no explicit reference to any final or culminating experience of S of a kind that S may consciously access and name. I do not wish to deny, however, that perceivings, veridical or not, are experiences (conscious or unconscious) undergone by perceivers, although it is not clear to me that they must always be reportable in the manner Snowdon at one time required. I have no qualms, that is, about the use of ‘perceives’ in my definition being taken to entail that, for any S, if S perceives O, S has an experience. I hope it will become clear as we proceed to what extent, if any, the terminological differences between our renderings of CTP matter.

  2. After all, an object’s “getting drier” isn’t itself actually separable in any obvious way from its proximate predecessors.

  3. See, for example, Grice 1961; Vision 1997, and Tye 2007.

  4. As can be seen, the addition of the phenomenological provision in CTP* allows the promise of sufficient, as well as necessary, conditions for perception. But no causal story is here being required for this “as if” state of affairs itself.

  5. In addition, it seems likely that formulation of the precise causal conditions that are alone sufficient to produce perception of O is tantamount to solving the ‘hard problem’ of consciousness.

  6. For defenses of disjunctivism, in addition to the two Snowdon papers discussed herein, see Hinton 1967 and 1973; McDowell 1982 and 2002; Putnam 1999; and Byrne and Logue 2009.

  7. Although I cannot make the case here, it is my view that the main defect in disjunctivism is not the claim that there may be no common epistemic factor between a merely ostensible and an apparently identical veridical perceptual experience; it is insisting that there can never be any such common factor.

  8. For defenses of CTP against other sorts of arguments, see Vision 1997 and Horn 2010.

References

  • Byrne and Logue (eds.). (2009). Disjunctivism: Contemporary readings. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

  • Grice, H. P. (1961). The causal theory of perception. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 35, 121–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hallett, H. F. (1949). On a reputed equivoque´ in the philosophy of Spinoza. The Review of Metaphysics, 3, 189–212.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, W. (2010). Reid and Hall on Perceptual Relativity and Error. Journal of Scottish Philosophy, 8(2), 115–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hinton, J. M. (1967). Visual experiences. Mind, 76, 217–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hinton, J. M. (1973). Experiences: An iInquiry into some ambiguities. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1982). Criteria, Defeasibility and Knowledge. Proceedings of the British Academy, 68, 455–479.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2002). Knowledge and the Internal Revisited. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 64, 97–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1999). The threefold cord. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snowdon, P. (1980-1981). Perception, vision, and causation. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 81, 175–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snowdon, P. (1990). The Objects of Perceptual Experience. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 64, 121–166.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (2007). Intentionalism and the Argument from no Common Content. Philosophical Perspectives, 21, 589–613.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vision, G. (1997). Problems of Vision. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Walter Horn.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Horn, W. Note on Two Snowdon Criticisms of the Causal Theory of Perception. Acta Anal 27, 441–447 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-011-0143-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-011-0143-z

Keywords

Navigation