Skip to main content
Log in

What Does the Nation of China Think About Phenomenal States?

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Critics of functionalism about the mind often rely on the intuition that collectivities cannot be conscious in motivating their positions. In this paper, we consider the merits of appealing to the intuition that there is nothing that it’s like to be a collectivity. We demonstrate that collective mentality is not an affront to commonsense, and we report evidence that demonstrates that the intuition that there is nothing that it’s like to be a collectivity is, to some extent, culturally specific rather than universally held. This being the case, we argue that mere appeal to the intuitive implausibility of collective consciousness does not offer any genuine insight into the nature of mentality in general, nor the nature of consciousness in particular.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. To our knowledge, the first occurrence of this question as a philosophical discussion of experience occurs in Farrell (1950). However, the example is likely to have a familiar history within the philosophy of mind.

  2. This includes work on psychological development, autism, and the social reasoning capacities of non-human primates. For an overview of the literature, as well as an interesting positive theory, see Nichols and Stich (2003).

  3. In a recent conversation, Steven Quartz, informed BH of the results of a recent fMRI study demonstrating that regions of the brain classically associated with the ascription of mental states were activated when participants made predictions about the behavior of a market. We contend that this data provides further evidence for the claim that the ascription of mental states to at least some collectivities recruits the mechanisms that are used in ascribing mental states to individuals.

  4. Knobe and Prinz (2008) conceive of phenomenal states in line with Block’s (1995) distinction between phenomenal-consciousness from access-consciousness. A mental state counts as access-conscious when it has a content in virtue of which it is poised for reasoning and rational control of action; it counts as phenomenally conscious when there is something that it is like for a subject to be in it. Block argues that phenomenal-consciousness is conceptually distinct from access-consciousness.

  5. An anonymous reviewer suggested that our claim is also weakened by the fact that the mean response of participants from CUHK for the ascriptions of phenomenal states to groups range from 3.71 to 4.71 on a 7-pt scale. So, although participants from CUHK were more willing than UNC participants to ascribe phenomenal states to groups, they did not judge group phenomenal states to be clearly natural. However, it is important to recall that participants from CUHK judged ascriptions of phenomenal states to groups to be no less natural than ascriptions of mental states to individuals, suggesting that the ‘intuitive’ disanalogy between collective and individual mental states may not be strong enough to motivate an objection to functionalism. Yet, the fact that even the ascriptions of mental states to individuals did not sound natural is troubling. Perhaps by presenting the questions in English—a second language—we offered a task in which none of the ascriptions seemed particularly natural. In order to examine the generality of our data, we conducted a follow-up study in Mandarin Chinese with 35 college age people at Shanghai University (a population less ‘Western’ than our Hong Kong sample) and 49 students from Boston University; these data were collected in accordance with the procedures required by the Institutional Review Board at Tufts University. Participants read 4 mental state ascriptions (two phenomenal, two non-phenomenal) and offered judgments on a 6-point scale. Unsurprisingly, participants at BU judged it acceptable to say that a corporation could ‘be happy’ (M = 3.17) but it could not ‘feel upset’ (M = 3.0)—replicating results reported by Knobe and Prinz (2008). However, our Shanghai participants judged that a corporation could ‘feel upset’ (M = 3.40) yet not ‘be happy’ (M = 2.69). Participants in Shanghai saw significant differences between the acceptability of the various mental state ascriptions, F(3, 102) = 4.82, p = .004. However, subsequent Bonferonni corrected post-hoc tests revealed only two significant differences (intending and planning, mean difference = 1.429, p = .014; intending and being happy, mean difference = 1.371, p = .043). Strikingly, this analysis revealed no significant difference between intending and feeling upset (mean difference = .657, p = 1.00). Thus, although these data replicated our finding that some so-called phenomenal states are rightly attributed to collectivities, there may be relevant differences that do not cleanly track the phenomenal/non-phenomenal distinction (cf., Sytsma and Machery, submitted). We thus suggest that the ascription of mental states to collectivities is sensitive to cultural considerations; however, the precise range of collective mental states that are acceptable will require further empirical analysis.

References

  • Allport, F. 1924. Social psychology. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ames, R. 1994. Reflections on the Confucian self. In Rules, rituals, and responsibility, ed. M. Bockover. LaSalle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arico, A., B. Fiala, R. Goldberg, and S. Nichols. Submitted. The folk psychology of consciousness.

  • Block, N. 1978. Troubles with functionalism. In Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, vol. IX, ed. C.W. Savage, 261–325. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. 1995. On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18: 227–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, P., and D. Kelemen. 1995. Syntactic cues in the acquisition of collective nouns. Cognition 56: 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, P., and C. Veres. 1999. The perceived intentionality of groups. Cognition 71: b1–b9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. 1874. Psychologie vom Empiriischen Standpunkt. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. 1996. The conscious mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. 1978. Intentional systems. In Brainstorms. Cambridge: Bradford Books: 3–22.

  • Dennett, D. 1987. True believers. In The intentional stance. Cambridge: MIT: 13–36.

  • Durkheim, E. 1895/1982. The rules of sociological method, ed. Steven Lukes and trans. WD Halls. London: Free Press.

  • Farrell, B. 1950. Experience. Mind 59: 170–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, D., and R. Ames. 1998. Thinking from the Han: Self, truth and transcendence in Chinese and Western Culture. Albany: SUNY.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heider, F., and M. Simmel. 1944. An experimental study of apparent behavior. American Journal of Psychology 57: 243–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huebner, B. 2008. Do you see what we see? An investigation of an argument against collective representation. Philosophical psychology 21: 91–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. Forthcoming. Varieties of externalism. In The extended mind, ed. R. Menary. Ashgate.

  • Kashima, Y., et al. 1995. Culture, gender, and self. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 69: 925–937.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kashima, Y., et al. 2005. Culture, essentialism, and agency. European Journal of Social Psychology 35: 147–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., and J. Prinz. 2008. Intuitions about consciousness: experimental studies. Phenomenology and Cognitive Science 7: 67–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S.M. 2006. On the evolution of human motivation: The role of Social Prosthetic Systems. In Evolutionary cognitive neuroscience, ed. S.M. Platek, T.K. Shackelford, and J.P. Keenan. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Le Bon, G. 1895/2002. The crowd. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, J. 1983. Materialism and qualia: the explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 64: 354–361.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. 1987. Consciousness. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malle, B.F. 1999. How people explain behavior: a new theoretical framework. Personality and Social Psychology Review 3: 23–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malle, B.F., and J. Knobe. 1997. The folk concept of intentionality. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 33: 101–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markus, H., and S. Kitayama. 1991. Culture and the self: implications for cognition, emotion, and motivation. Psychological Review 98: 224–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDougall, W. 1920. The group mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menon, T., et al. 1999. Culture and the construal of agency. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 76: 701–717.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Minsky, M. 1988. Society of the mind. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, M., T. Menon, and D. Ames. 2001. Culturally conferred conceptions of agency: a key to social perception of persons, groups, and other actors. Personality and Social Psychology Review 5: 169–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., and S. Stich. 2003. Mindreading. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. 1887/1998. On the genealogy of morality (trans: Clark, M. and A. Swensen). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

  • Nisbett, R., et al. 2001. Culture and systems of thought. Psychological Review 108: 291–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O'Laughlin, M.J., and B.F. Malle. 2002. How people explain actions performed by groups and individuals. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 82:33–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosemont, H. 1991. Rights-bearing individuals and role-bearing persons. In Rules, rituals, and responsibility, ed. M. Bockover. LaSalle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J., and E. Machery. 2009. How to study folk intuitions about phenomenal consciousness. Philosophical Psychology 22: 21–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J., and E. Machery. Forthcoming. Two conceptions of subjective experience. Philosophical Studies.

  • Varela, F., E. Thompson, and E. Rosch. 1991. The embodied mind. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, T., and D. Wegner. 1995. Transactive memory. In The Blackwell encyclopedia of social psychology, ed. A. Manstead, and M. Hewstone. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The authors would like to thank Adam Arico, Joshua Knobe, Shaun Nichols, Orion Richardson, Rob Rupert, Susanne Sreedhar, and the audiences at the Society for Philosophy and Psychology (Toronto 2007) and the Center for Human Sciences (Chapel Hill 2007).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bryce Huebner.

Appendix 1: Experimental Materials

Appendix 1: Experimental Materials

1.1 Experiment 1

The Ming Dynasty felt relief after the rebellion was quelled.

Denmark feels embarrassed about losing the war.

Destiny’s Child is feeling insecure after its poor performance last night.

The Catholic Church is vividly imagining the crucifixion.

Sony is experiencing great joy at its increased sales.

The Ming Dynasty thought that China was the greatest country in the world.

Denmark is proud of its Viking heritage.

Destiny’s Child wants to put on a better show tomorrow night.

The Catholic Church knows that Christmas is coming soon.

Sony intends to release a new product in January to increase sales.

Tanya feels relieved after her mother’s successful surgery

Agassi felt embarrassed after he lost the tennis match.

Paul McCartney is feeling insecure after his poor performance last night.

That bee is vividly imagining honey.

Dmitri is experiencing great joy at his new job.

Tanya believes that China is the greatest country in the world.

Agassi is proud of his American heritage.

Paul McCartney wants to put on a better show tomorrow night.

That bee knows where the honey is located.

Dmitri intends to start selling winter hats in January

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Huebner, B., Bruno, M. & Sarkissian, H. What Does the Nation of China Think About Phenomenal States?. Rev.Phil.Psych. 1, 225–243 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-009-0009-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-009-0009-0

Keywords

Navigation