Skip to main content
Log in

Tacit and accessible understanding of language

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The empirical nature of our understanding of language is explored. I first show that there are several important and different distinctions between tacit and accessible awareness. I then present empirical evidence concerning our understanding of language. The data suggests that our awareness of sentence-meanings is sometimes merely tacit according to one of these distinctions, but is accessible according to another. I present and defend an interpretation of this mixed view. The present project is shown to impact on several diverse areas, including inferential role semantics and holism, the nature of learning, and the role of linguistics in the law.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Anderson R. and Pichert J. (1978). Recall of previously unrecallable information following a shift in perspective. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 17: 1–12

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baker M. (1988). Incorporation. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker M. (2003). Lexical categories. CUP, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Bittner M. (1999). Concealed causatives. Natural Language Semantics 7: 1–78

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block N. (1995). On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18: 227–287

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloom P. and Keil F. (2001). Thinking through language. Linguistics and Philosophy 16: 351–367

    Google Scholar 

  • Boroditsky L. (2001). Does language shape thought? Mandarin and English speakers conceptions of time. Cognitive Psychology 43: 1–22

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bresnan J.J. (1982). The mental representation of grammatical relations. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky N. (1965). Aspects of the theory of syntax. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky N. (1981). Lectures on government and binding. Foris, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky N. (1995). The minimalist program. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky N. (2000). Minimalist inquiries: The framework. In: Martin, R. (eds) Step by step: essays on minimalist syntax in honor of howard lasnik, pp 89–155. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky N. (2001). Derivation by phase. In: Kenstowicz, M. (eds) Ken Hale, pp 1–52. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Comrie B. (1985). Causative verb formation and other verb-deriving morphology. In: Shopen, T. (eds) Language typology and syntactic description, pp 309–348. CUP, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Connolly T., Arkes H. and Hammond K. (2000). Judgment and decision making. CUP, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Cosmides L. and Tooby J. (1992). The adapted mind. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Crimmins M. (1992). Tacitness and virtual beliefs. Mind and Language 7: 240–263

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Culicover P. (1997). Principles and parameters. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1967a). Truth and meaning. Reprinted in Davidson 1984, pp. 17–36.

  • Davidson, D. (1967b). The logical form of action sentences. Reprinted in Davidson 1980, pp. 105–122.

  • Davidson, D. (1967c). Causal relations. Reprinted in Davidson 1980, pp. 149–162.

  • Davidson D. (1970a). Action and reaction. Inquiry 13: 140–148

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1970b). Semantics for natural languages. Reprinted in Davidson 1984, pp. 55–64.

  • Davidson, D. (1974). Belief and the basis of meaning. Reprinted in Davidson 1984, pp. 141–154.

  • Davidson D. (1984). Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowty D. (1979). Word meaning and montague grammar. D. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1975). What is a theory of meaning? (I), in Dummett 1993, pp. 1–33.

  • Dummett, M. (1978). What do I know when I know a language?, in Dummett 1993, pp. 94–105.

  • Dummett M. (1993). The seas of language. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Falk Y. (2001). Lexical-functional grammar. Stanford, CSLI

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J. (1998). In critical condition. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J. (2001). Language, thought and compositionality. Linguistics and philosophy 16: 1–15

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J. and Lepore E. (1992). Holism: a shopper’s guide. Blackwell’s, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • George A. (1989). How not to become confused about linguistics. In: George, A. (eds) Reflections on Chomsky, pp 90–110. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilovich T., Griffin D. and Kahneman (2002). Heuristics and biases: The psychology of intuitive judgement. CUP, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Haegeman L. (1994). Introduction to government and binding theory. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hale, K., & Keyser, S. (1987). A View from the Middle, Lexicon Project Working Papers 10, Cambridge, MA: Center for Cognitive Science, MIT.

  • Hale K. and Keyser S. (1993). On argument structure and the lexical expression of syntactic relations. In: Hale, K. and Keyser, S. (eds) The view from building, 20, pp 53–109. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman G. (1973). Thought. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1993). Meaning holism defended. In J. Fodor & E. Lepore (Eds.), Holism: A consumer’s update, Amsterdam: Rodopi.

  • Hart H. and Honoré A. (1959). Causation and the law. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hess E. (1965). Attitude and pupil size. Scientific American 212: 46–54

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hess E. (1975). The role of pupil size in communication. Scientific American 233: 110–119

    Google Scholar 

  • Higginbotham, J. (1985). On semantics. Reprinted in E. Lepore (Ed.), New directions in semantics (pp. 1–54). London: Academic Press. 1987.

  • Higginbotham J. (1989). Elucidations of meaning. Linguistics and Philosophy 12: 465–517

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Higginbotham, J. (1994). Priorities in the philosophy of thought. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supp. vol. 20, 85–106.

  • Higginbotham, J. (1998). Conceptual competence. In E. Villanueva (Ed.), Concepts (pp. 149–162). Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hornstein, N. (2003). On control. In R. Hendrick (Ed.), Minimalist Syntax (pp. 6–81). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson K. (2004a). Tacit belief, semantics and grammar. Linguistics and Philosophy 27: 57–91

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson K. (2004b). From impossible words to conceptual structure: The role of structure and processes in the Lexicon. Mind and Language 19: 334–358

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larson R. and Segal G. (1995). Knowledge of Meaning. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin B. and Rappaport Hovav M. (1995). Unaccusativity: At the syntax–lexical semantics interface. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D. (1973). Causation. Journal of Philosophy 70: 556–567

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loftus E. and Hoffman H. (1989). Misinformation and memory, the creation of new memories. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 118: 100–104

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loftus, E., & Ketcham, K. (1994). The myth of repressed memory. NY: St. Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maibom H. (2003). The mindreader and the scientist. Mind and Language 18: 296–315

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maier N. (1931). Reasoning in Humans, II. Journal of Comparative Psychology 12: 181–194

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marcel A. (1989). Phenomenal experience and functionalism. In: Marcel, A.J. and Bisiach, E. (eds) Consciousness in contemporary science, pp 121–158. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcel, A. (1993). Slippage in the unity of consciousness. In G. Bock & J. Marsh (Eds.), Experimental and Theoretical Studies of Consciousness (pp. 283–300). Chichester: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller G. and Johnson-Laird P. (1976). Language and perception. CUP, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy G. and Shapiro A. (1994). Forgetting of Verbatim Information in Discourse. Memory and Cognition 22: 85–94

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel T. (1969). Linguistics and epistemology. In: Hook, S. (eds) Language and philosophy, pp 171–182. NYU Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Nisbett R. and DeCamp Wilson T. (1977). Telling more than we can know: verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review 84: 231–259

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Owens J., Bower G. and Black J. (1979). The ‘Soap Opera’ effect in story recall. Memory and Cognition 7: 185–191

    Google Scholar 

  • Parsons T. (1990). Events in the semantics of english. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1975). Truth definitions and actual languages. In G. Evans & J. McDowell (Eds.), Truth and meaning (pp. 162–188). Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke C. (1992). A study of concepts. IT Press, Cambridge MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietroski P. (1998). Actions, adjuncts and agency. Mind 107: 73–111

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pietroski P. (2000). Causing actions. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Plaut D. (2003). Connectionist modeling of language: Examples and implications. In: Banich, M. and Mack, M. (eds) Mind, brain and language, pp 143–167. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Mahwah, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz J. (2002). Furnishing the mind. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky J. (1991). The syntax of event structure. Cognition 41: 47–81

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sachs J. (1967). Recognition memory for syntactic and semantic aspects of connected discourse. Perception and Psychophysics 2: 437–442

    Google Scholar 

  • Schacter, D. (1989). On the relation between memory and consciousness: dissociable interactions and conscious experience. In H. L. Roediger III & F. I. M. Craik (Eds.), Varieties of memory and consciousness: essays in honor of Endel Tulving (pp. 355–389). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars W. (1974). Meaning as functional classification. Synthese 27: 417–437

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simons D. and Chabris C. (1999). Gorillas in our midst: sustained inattentional blindness for dynamic events. Perception 28: 1059–1074

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stich S. (1978). Beliefs and subdoxastic states. Philosophy of Science 45: 499–518

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tenny C. (1994). Aspectual roles and the syntax-semantics interface. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Tiersma P. and Solan L. (2002). The Linguist on the witness stand: forensic linguistics in american courts. Language 78: 221–239

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trivers, R. (1985). Social evolution. Reading, MA.: Benjamin/Cummings.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vision G. (1998). Blindsight and philosophy. Philosophical Psychology 11: 137–159

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical Investigations (G. E. M. Anscombe, transl.). New York: Macmillan and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, C. (1986). Theories of meaning and speaker’s knowledge. In Realism, meaning and truth (2nd ed., pp. 204–238). Oxford: Blackwell, 1993.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kent Johnson.

Additional information

I am indebted to a number of people for their useful feedback, especially Peter Ludlow, Paul Pietroski, and two anonymous reviewers. Earlier versions of this paper were presented at an Eastern meeting of the APA, a meeting of the Society for Exact Philosophy at Simon Fraser University, and at a semantics workshop in Ottawa, Canada. I greatly appreciate the comments from those audiences.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Johnson, K. Tacit and accessible understanding of language. Synthese 156, 253–279 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-006-0006-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-006-0006-0

Keywords

Navigation