Skip to main content
Log in

Evolutionary debunking arguments against theism, reconsidered

  • Article
  • Published:
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Evolutionary debunking arguments (EDAs) against religious beliefs move from the claim that religious beliefs are caused by off-track processes to the conclusion that said religious beliefs are unjustified and/or false. Prima facie, EDAs commit the genetic fallacy, unduly conflating the context of discovery and the context of justification. In this paper, we first consider whether EDAs necessarily commit the genetic fallacy, and if not, whether modified EDAs (e.g., those that posit falsehood-tracking or perniciously deceptive belief-forming mechanisms) provide successful arguments against theism. Then, we critically evaluate more recent attempts to argue that a more promiscuous evolutionary scepticism renders religious belief unjustified because, unlike commonsense and scientific beliefs, religious beliefs have no way out of such scepticism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This raises the question of what truth-tracking consists in. Kahane (2011) does not specify, instead assuming “an intuitive understanding of the epistemic premise (such an understanding doesn’t require a positive account of truth-tracking processes)”. Presumably, however, he has something like Nozick’s (1981) account in mind, in which:

    1. (1)

      p is true

    2. (2)

      S believes p

    3. (3)

      if p were not true then S would not believe that p, and

    4. (4)

      if p were true then S would believe that p (and would not believe that not-p).

  2. Indeed, for epistemic externalists, reasons could count as causes; good reasons would thus be epistemically respectable causes

  3. After all, Griffith and Wilkins’s (2013) inference to the best explanation is itself in the dock under this radical evolutionary scepticism.

  4. Some classical theists may object that God is not an “unobservable causal entity”, nor indeed an entity of any kind (cf. Davies 1985; Mascall 1943). The philosophical significance of this theological assertion is under-explored in contemporary attempts to put science and theism in conversation.

  5. This is not to deny that Swinburne thinks that religious experiences have a role to play in justifying religious belief. Indeed, Swinburne argues that “One who has had a religious experience apparently of God has, by the Principle of Credulity, good reason for believing that there is a God—other things being equal” (p. 324). But what if things are not equal? Swinburne concedes, as we do, that one who has had a religious experience but has other reasons to believe “that it is significantly more probable than not that there is no God” (p. 326) is not justified in believing that there is God. But what if it can be shown that “special considerations”—such as the influence of hallucinogens—render one’s religious experience questionable? Swinburne concedes, as we do, that the religious experience would not provide sufficient reason for believing that there is a God. However, neither Swinburne nor we believe that everything rides on the religious experience. Even if the religious experience itself fails to provide sufficient reason for believing that there is a God, other arguments are available. The validity and soundness of these arguments are not affected by the reason-providing poverty of the religious experience.

  6. This is probably the reason why much of the EDA debate in philosophy of religion has so far been preoccupied with defending the truth-tracking nature of the cognitive mechanisms that (according to CSR) produce theistic beliefs. See, for example Clark and Barrett (2011), Murray (2009), and Murray and Goldberg (2009).

References

  • Atran, S. (2002). In gods we trust: The evolutionary landscape of religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, J. (2004). Why would anyone believe in God?. Walnut Creek: AltaMira Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beilby, J. (Ed.). (2002). Naturalism defeated?. Essays on Plantinga’s evolutionary argument against naturalism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

  • Benfey, O. T. (1958). August kekulé and the birth of the structural theory of organic chemistry in 1858. Journal of Chemical Education, 35I, 21–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bering, J. (2011). The God instinct: The psychology of souls destiny and the meaning of life. London: Nicholas Brealey Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (1980). Externalist theories of empirical knowledge. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5, 53–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyer, P. (2001). Religion explained: The evolutionary origins of religious thought. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brosnan, K. (2011). Do the evolutionary origins of our moral beliefs undermine moral knowledge? Biology and Philosophy, 26, 51–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, K., & Barrett, J. (2011). Reidian religious epistemology and the cognitive science of religion. The Journal of the American Academy of Religion, 79, 639–675.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1881). Letter 3230–Charles Darwin to William Graham 3 July 1881. Retrieved from http://www.darwinprojectacuk/entry-13230 on March 5 2012

  • Davies, B. (1985). Thinking about God. London: Geoffrey Chapman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawes, G. W., & Jong, J. (2012). Defeating the christian’s claim to warrant. Philo, 15, 127–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Cruz, H., Boudry, M., De Smedt, J., & Blancke, S. (2011). Evolutionary approaches to epistemic justification. Dialectica, 64, 517–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (2006). Breaking the spell: Religion as a natural phenomenon. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1986). Epistemology and cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (2008). Immediate justification and process reliabilism. In J. Smith (Ed.), Epistemology: New essays (pp. 63–82). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P., & Wilkins, J. (2013). Evolutionary debunking arguments in three domains: Fact value and religion. In G. Dawes & J. Maclaurin (Eds.), A new science of religion (pp. 133–146). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene, P. (2006). Context of discovery versus context of justification and thomas kuhn. Archimedes, 14, 119–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (2008). Dialogues and Natural history of religion. J. C. A. Gaskin (Ed.), Oxford:Oxford University Press. (Original work published 1757).

  • Jong, J. (2012). Explaining religion (away?): Theism and the cognitive science of religion. Sophia, 52, 521–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. (2006). The evolution of morality. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahane, G. (2011). Evolutionary debunking arguments. Noûs, 45, 103–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klement, K. (2002). When is genetic reasoning not fallacious? Argumentation, 16, 383–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leech, D., & Visala, A. (2011). The cognitive science of religion: A modified theist response. Religious Studies, 47, 301–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leech, D., & Visala, A. (2012). How relevant is the cognitive science of religion to philosophy of religion. In: Y. Nagasawa (Ed.), Scientific approaches to the philosophy of religion. Basingstoke:Palgrave.

  • Mascall, E. L. (1943). He who is. London: Darton, Longman & Todd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murray, M. (2009). Scientific explanations of religion and the justification of religious belief. In M. J. Murray & J. Schloss (Eds.), The believing primate: Scientific philosophical and theological reflections on the origin of religion (pp. 168–177). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Murray, M., & Goldberg, A. (2009). Evolutionary accounts of religion: Explaining and explaining. In M. J. Murray & J. Schloss (Eds.), The believing primate: Scientific philosophical and theological reflections on the origin of religion (pp. 179–199). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1993). Warrant and proper function. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Plantinga, A. (2000). Warranted Christian belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (2011). Where the conflict really lies?. Oxford: Science religion and naturalism Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1938). Experience and prediction. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M . (2006). Evolutionary ethics and contemporary biology. In G. Boniolo & G. de Anna (Eds.), Is Darwinian metaethics possible (and if it is is it well-taken)? (pp. 13–26). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Ruse, M. (2009). Evolution and ethics: The sociobiological approach. In M. Ruse (Ed.), Philosophy after Darwin (pp. 489–511). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1970). Bayes’s theorem and the history of science. In R. Stuewer (Ed.), Historical and philosophical perspectives of science (pp. 68–85). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1984). Logic. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, H. (1980). Justification discovery and the naturalizing of epistemology. Philosophy of Science, 47, 297–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (2004). The existence of God (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. (2006). A darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127, 109–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tremlin, T. (2006). Minds and gods: The cognitive foundations of religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, D. S. (2002). Darwin’s cathedral: Evolution religion and the nature of society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jonathan Jong.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Jong, J., Visala, A. Evolutionary debunking arguments against theism, reconsidered. Int J Philos Relig 76, 243–258 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-014-9461-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-014-9461-6

Keywords

Navigation