Skip to main content
Log in

Hans Reichenbach's relativity of geometry

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Hans Reichenbach's 1928 thesis of the relativity of geometry has been misunderstood as the statement that the geometrical structure of space can be described in different languages. In this interpretation the thesis becomes an instance of ‘trivial semantical conventionalism’, as Grünbaum calls it. To understand Reichenbach correctly, we have to interpret it in the light of the linguistic turn, the transition from ‘thought oriented philosophy’ to ‘language oriented philosophy’, which mainly took place in the first decades of our century. Reichenbach — as Poincaré before him — is undermining the prejudice of thought oriented philosophy, that two propositions have different factual content, if they are associated with different ideas in our mind. Thus Reichenbach prepared the change to language oriented philosophy, which he also accepted later.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Bibliography

  • Carnap, R., 1926, Physikalische Begriffsbildung, Braun, Karlsruhe; reprint: Wissenschaftliche Buchges., Darmstadt, 1966.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R., 1928, Der logische Aufbau der Welt, Berlin-Schlachtensee; reprint: Meiner, Hamburg, 1961.

  • Carnap, R., 1958, ‘Introductory Remarks to the English Edition’ in PST, pp. v–vii; German translation in Reichenbach (1976).

  • Carnap, R., 1963, ‘Intellectual Autobiography’, in P. A. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, Open Court, La Salle (Ill.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Grelling, K., 1930, ‘Die Philosophie der Raum-Zeit-Lehre’, (extensive review), Philosophischer Anzeiger 4, 101–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grünbaum, A., 1963, Philosophical Problems of Space and Time, Knopf, New York; 2nd edition: 1973, Reidel, Dordrecht-Boston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grünbaum, A., 1968, Geometry and Chronometry in Philosophical Perspective, Univ. of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grünbaum, A., 1976, ‘Absolute and Relational Theories of Space and Space-Time’, in Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 8, Univ. of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Helmholtz, H. v., 1962, Popular Scientific Lectures, Dover, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jørgensen, J., 1951, ‘The Development of Logical Empiricism’, Int. Encycl. of Unif. Science 2, No. 9, Univ. of Chicago Press, Chicago-London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamlah, A., 1976, ‘Erläuterungen, Bemerkungen und Verweise’, in Reichenbach (1976), Vol. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kretzmann, N., 1967, ‘Semantics, History of’, in P. Edwards (ed.), The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Macmillan, New York-London, Vol. 7, pp. 358–406.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pap, A., 1949, Elements of Analytic Philosophy, Macmillan, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H., 1963, ‘An Examination of Grünbaum's Philosophy of Geometry’, in B. Baumrin (ed.), Philosophy of Science, The Delaware Seminar, Vol. 2, Interscience, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, H., 1914, Science and Method, London.

  • Reichenbach, H., 1928, Philosophie der Raum-Zeit-Lehre, de Gruyter, Berlin; 2. ed. Reichenbach (1976), vol. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H., 1929, ‘Ziele und Wege der physikalischen Erkenntnis’, in H. Geiger and K. Scheel (eds.), Handbuch der Physik, Springer, Berlin, Vol. 4, pp. 1–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H., 1951, The Rise of Scientific Philosophy, Univ. of California Press, Berkeley-Los Angeles; German translation: Reichenbach (1965); 2. ed.: Reichenbach (1976), vol. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H., 1958 (PST) Philosophy of Space and Time, Dover, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H., 1965, Der Aufstieg der wissenschaftlichen Philosophie (translation of Reichenbach, 1951), Vieweg, Braunschweig.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H., 1976, Gesammelte Werke in 9 Bänden, Vieweg, Braunschweig-Wiesbaden; Vol. 1: Reichenbach (1965); Vol. 2: Reichenbach (1928).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R., (ed.), 1967, The Linguistic Turn. Recent Essays in Philosophical Method, Chicago-London.

  • Russell, B., 1926, Unser Wissen von der Auβenwelt (German translation of Our Knowledge of the External World), Meiner, Leipzig.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schleichert, H., (ed.), 1975, Logischer Empirismus-Der Wiener Kreis (Essays of the Vienna Circle) Fink, München.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlick, M., 1918, Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre, springer, Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlick, M., 1925, 2. edition of Schlick (1918).

  • Schlick, M., 1949, ‘Meaning and Verification’, from Philosophical Revue 44 (1936); reprinted in H. Feigl and W. Sellars (eds.), Readings in Philosophical Analysis, Appleton Century Crofts, New York, pp. 146–170.

  • Schlick, M., 1974, General Theory of Knowledge (transl. of Schlick, 1918, 2nd edition) Springer, Wien-New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitbeck, C., 1969, ‘Simultaneity and Distance’, Journal of Philosophy 66, 329–340.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kamlah, A. Hans Reichenbach's relativity of geometry. Synthese 34, 249–263 (1977). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00485877

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00485877

Keywords

Navigation