Skip to main content
Log in

Autonoesis and Belief in a Personal Past: An Evolutionary Theory of Episodic Memory Indices

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I discuss philosophical and psychological treatments of the question “how do we decide that an occurrent mental state is a memory and not, say a thought or imagination?” This issue has proven notoriously difficult to resolve, with most proposed indices, criteria and heuristics failing to achieve consensus. Part of the difficulty, I argue, is that the indices and analytic solutions thus far offered seldom have been situated within a well-specified theory of memory function. As I hope to show, when such an approach is adopted, not only does a new, functionally-grounded answer emerge; we also gain insight into the adaptive significance of the process proposed to underwrite our belief in the memorial status of a mental state (i.e., autonoetic awareness).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The view that memory is reconstructive characterizes “academic” psychological research, not psychological research in general. Among clinicians and neuroscientists memory is just as likely to be taken as a stable transcription of events as they originally transpired. Despite (a) Freud’s realization that what initially he believed were patients’ “true” recollections actually were fantasies (e.g., Schimek 1987), and (b), that after nearly a century (e.g., Penfield 1952), neuroscience finally appears ready to entertain the possibility that memory may not constitute a fixed transcription of the past (e.g., Schiller et al. 2010), the belief that recollection is underwritten by verdicial records still is the norm among these two disciplines.

  2. Interestingly, in antiquity memory was not taken to be a stable record of the past (e.g., Rubin 1995). It only was with the advent of transcription technology (e.g., writing, printing, cameras, tape recorders, computers, and so on) that the metaphor of permanence became part of our conception of the nature of memory (for discussion see Danziger 2008).

  3. The expanded temporality of the specious present represents time as moving toward the future as well as receding into the past (e.g., Husserl 1964; James 1890). On this basis, one might be concerned that I arbitrarily have chosen to focus on the future aspect of the specious present while ignoring its equally salient past aspect.

    Two considerations inform my temporal focus. First, the principles of evolutionary functionality discussed earlier (see also Klein 2013b) argue that memory is shaped by selective pressures to deal with the oncoming contingencies, and thus oriented toward the future. In addition, the 2nd law of thermodynamics entails that physical laws are not symmetric to reversal of time’s direction. Put simply, there is an “arrow of time” and it points in the direction of the future. Thus while past and future both are constituents of the specious present, the future aspect is accorded a privileged position in virtue of its relation to the law of cause and effect, entropy, etc.

    In short, the contingent necessities of life as well as physical laws support my contention that the temporally relevant direction for a behaving organism (and hence for memory) is the future, not the past.

  4. A discussion of relation between future-oriented mental time travel (FMTT) and episodic memory would take us far afield. However, a few remarks will be helpful.

    Despite clear theoretical argument and empirical demonstration that the future-oriented aspect of episodic memory is not the sole memory-based contributor to future-oriented temporal projection (e.g., Atance and O’Neill 2001; Klein et al. 2002), until recently FMTT research has been almost exclusively focused on the episodic aspects of FMTT. Only in the past few years have the contributions of semantic memory (as well as those of other cognitive mechanisms – e.g., Suddendorf et al. 2009) been recognized as critical aspects of future-oriented thought (for recent reviews, see Klein 2013c; Schacter 2012).

    Accordingly, there is no reason to suppose that episodic memory bears a special relation to future-oriented cognition. Even when projective acts are self-referential (as opposed to impersonal imaginations about the state of the future), it now is known that patients lacking complete access to episodic memory can perform imaginative acts that entail the involvement of self in a future scenario (a recent summary of relevant data can be found in Klein 2013a, c).

    What is special about episodic memory is that it alone among systems of memory is capable of directly presenting its owner the feeling that she or he is re-experiencing events from his or her past (more on this in Section 5). For remainder of this paper I will be concerned with this unique property of episodic memory. A more detailed treatment of the arguments for autonoetic functionality presented in this paper and their comparison with arguments of adaptive functionality that trade on the presumption of autonetic contributions to planning will be the subject of a forthcoming paper I am working on in conjunction with Endel Tulving.

  5. There has been recent movement to incorporate the future-orientation of memory into the mainstream research agenda (e.g., work on adaptive memory; for review see Nairine 2010, and future-oriented mental time travel; for reviews see Klein 2013a; Schacter 2012). These new approaches, however, remain exceptions to the received view that memory primarily is about the past.

  6. Note: It is very important to keep in mind that episodic recollection is a subset (albeit a salient one) of the activities associated with episodic memory. The recollective act reunites the individual with his or her past. Other functions of episodic memory (e.g., foresight, simulation, self-projection) have a decidedly future orientation (for recent reviews see Addis and Schacter 2012; Klein 2013a). However, these functions are not unique to episodic memory. The recollective act, by contrast, is.

References

  • Addis, D.R., and D.L. Schacter. 2012. The hippocampus and imagining the future: Where do we stand? Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 5: 173.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, J.R. 1991. Is human cognition adaptive? Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14: 471–517.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atance, C.M., and D.K. O’Neill. 2001. Episodic future thinking. Trends in Cognitive Science 5: 533–539.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bar, M. 2011. Predictions and the brain: Using our past to generate a future. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barkow, J.H., L. Cosmides, and J. Tooby (eds.). 1992. The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartlett, F.C. 1932. Remembering. London: Cambridge at The University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Begg, I., S. Duft, P. Lalonde, R. Melnick, and J. Sanvito. 1989. Memory predictions based on ease of processing. Journal of Memory and Language 28: 610–632.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benjamin, A.S., and R.A. Bjork. 1996. Retrieval fluency as a metacognitive index. In Implicit memory and metacognition, ed. L.M. Reder, 309–338. Hillsdale: Erlbaum Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernecker, S. 2010. Memory: A philosophical study. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berntsen, D. 2009. Involuntary autobiographical memories: An introduction to the unbidden past. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bischof-Koehler, D. 1985. On the phylogeny of human motivation. In Emotion and reflexivity, ed. L.H. Eckensberger and E.D. Lantermann, 3–47. Vienna: Urban & Schwarzenberg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohr, N. 1958. Atomic physics and human knowledge. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyer, P. 2009. What are memories for? Functions of recall in cognition and culture. In Memory in mind and culture, ed. P. Boyer and J.V. Wertsch, 3–28. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, F.H. 1887. Why do we remember forwards and not backwards? Mind 12: 579–582.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brunswik, E. 1947/1956. Perception and the representative design of psychological experiments. Berkeley: University of California Press.

  • Butler, J. 1736/1819. Of personal identity. In The analogy of religion, ed. J. Angus, 211–215. London: Allman and Sawers.

  • Cheke, L.G., and N.S. Clayton. 2010. Mental time travel in animals. WIREs Cogntive Science 1: 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coburn, R.C. 1960. A defect in Harrod’s inductive justification of memory. Philosophical Studies 11: 81–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conway, M.A. 2005. Memory and the self. Journal of Memory and Language 53: 594–628.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cosmides, L., and J. Tooby. 1992. Cognitive adaptations for social exchange. In The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture, ed. J. Barkow, L. Cosmides, and J. Tooby, 163–228. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danziger, K. 2008. Marking the mind: A history of memory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. 1976. The selfish gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Brigard, F. 2013. Is memory for remembering? Recollection as a form of episodic hypothetical thinking. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-013-0247-7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Draaisma, D. 2000. Metaphors of mind: A history of ideas about the mind. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J.C. 2004. Remember-know: A matter of confidence. Psychological Review 111: 524–542.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunlosky, L., and R.A. Bjork. 2008. Handbook of metamemory and memory. New York: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunlosky, J., and T.O. Nelson. 1992. Importance of the kind of cue for judgments of learning (JOLs) and the delayed-JOL effect. Memory and Cognition 20: 373–380.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faye, J. 1989. The reality of the future. Odense: Odense University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fivush, R., and C.A. Haden. 2003. Autobiographical memory and the construction of a narrative self. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Furlong, E.J. 1948. Memory. Mind 57: 16–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Furlong, E.J. 1951. A study in memory: A philosophical essay. London: Thomas Nelson and Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Furlong, E.J. 1970. Mr. Urmson on memory and imagination. Mind 79: 137–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glenberg, A.M. 1997. What memory is for? Behavioral and Brain Sciences 20: 1–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. 2003. Theory and reality. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heisenberg, W. 1958/1999. Physics and philosophy. Amherst: Prometheus Books.

  • Holland, R.F. 1954. The empiricist theory of memory. Mind 63: 464–486.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howe, M.L. 2013. Securing the future by remembering the past: But just when does this past and future begin to develop? Journal of Applied Research in Memory and Cognition 2(4): 237–239.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. 1748/2004. An enquiry concerning human understanding. New York: Dover Publications.

  • Husserl, E. 1964. The phenomenology of internal time-consciousness. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ingvar, D.H. 1985. Memory of the future: An essay on the temporal orientation of conscious awareness. Human Neurobiology 4: 127–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. 1890. Principles of psychology. New York: Henry Holt and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M.K., & Raye, C.L. (1981). Reality monitoring. Psychological Review 88: 67–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M.K., M.A. Foley, A.G. Suengas, and C.L. Raye. 1988. Phenomenal characteristics of memories for perceived and imagined autobiographical events. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 117: 371–376.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelley, C.M., and L.L. Jacoby. 1996. Memory attributions: Subjective experience versus analytic bases for judgments. Journal of Memory and Language 35: 157–175.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, E.R. 1882. The alternative: A study of psychology. London: Macmillian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. 1998. Mind in a physical world: An essay on the mind-body problem and mental causation. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klee, R. 1997. Introduction to the philosophy of science: Cutting nature at its seams. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, S.B. 2007. Phylogeny and evolution: Implications for understanding the nature of a memory system. In Science of memory: Concepts, ed. H.L. Roediger, Y. Dudai, and S. Fitzgerald, 377–381. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, S.B. 2013a. Making the case that episodic recollection is attributable to operations occurring at retrieval rather than to content stored in a dedicated subsystem of long-term memory. Frontiers in Behavioral Neuroscience 7: 3. doi:10.3389/fnbeh.2013.00003

  • Klein, S.B. 2013b. The temporal orientation of memory: It’s time for a change of direction. Journal of Research in Applied Memory and Cognition 2: 222–234.

  • Klein, S.B. 2013c. The complex act of projecting oneself into the future. WIREs Cognitive Sciences 4: 63–79.

  • Klein, S.B. 2013d. The sense of diachronic personal identity. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 12: 791–811.

  • Klein, S.B. 2014. The two selves: Their metaphysical commitments and functional independence. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Klein, S.B., and C.E. Gangi 2010. The multiplicity of self: Neuropsychological evidence and its implications for the self as a construct in psychological research. The Year in Cognitive Neuroscience 2010: Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1191, 1–15.

  • Klein, S.B., and M.L. Lax. 2010. The unanticipated resilience of trait self-knowledge in the face of neural damage. Memory 18: 918–948.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, S.B., and S. Nichols. 2012. Memory and the sense of personal identity. Mind 121: 677–702.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, S.B., J. Loftus, and H.A. Burton. 1989. Two self-reference effects: The importance of distinguishing between self-descriptiveness judgments and autobiographical retrieval in self-referent encoding. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 56: 853–865.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, S.B., L. Cosmides, J. Tooby, and S. Chance. 2001. Priming exceptions: A test of the scope hypothesis in naturalistic trait judgments. Social Cognition 19: 443–468.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, S.B., L. Cosmides, J. Tooby, and S. Chance. 2002. Decisions and the evolution of memory: Multiple systems, multiple functions. Psychological Review 109: 306–329.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, S.B., L. Cosmides, C.E. Gangi, B. Jackson, J. Tooby, and K.A. Costabile. 2009. Evolution and episodic memory: An analysis and demonstration of a social function of episodic recollection. Social Cognition 27: 283–319.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, S.B., T.E. Robertson, and A.W. Delton. 2010. Facing the future: Memory as an evolved system for planning future acts. Memory & Cognition 38: 13–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, S.B., T.E. Roberson, and A.W. Delton. 2011. The future-orientation of memory: Planning as a key component mediating the high levels of recall found with survival processing. Memory 19: 121–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kopelman, M.D., B.A. Wilson, and A.D. Baddeley. 1989. The autobiographical memory interview: A new assessment of autobiographical and personal semantic memory in amnesic patients. Journal of Clinical and Experimental Neuropsychology 11: 724–744.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koriat, A. 2000. The feeling of knowing: Some metatheoretical implications for consciousness and control. Consciousness and Cognition 9: 149–171.

    Google Scholar 

  • Llinas, R.R. 2001. I of the vortex: From neuron to self. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. 1689-1700/1975. An essay concerning human understanding. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Loftus, E.F., and H.G. Hoffman. 1989. Misinformation and memory: The creation of memory. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 118: 100–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loftus, E.F., and J.E. Pickrell. 1995. The formation of false memories. Psychiatric Annals 25: 720–725.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loizou, A. 1986. The reality of time. Aldershot: Gower Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ludlow, P. 1995. Social externalism and memory: A problem? Acta Analytica 10: 69–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Markowitsch, H.J. 2003. Autonoetic consciousness. In The self in neuroscience and psychiatry, ed. T. Kircher and A. David, 180–196. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Markowitsch, H.J., and A. Staniliou. 2011. Memory, autonoetic consciousness, and the self. Consciousness and Cognition 20: 16–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martinelli, P., M. Sperduti, and P. Piolino. 2013. Neural substrates of the self- memory system: New insights from a meta-analysis. Human Brain Mapping 34: 1515–1529. doi:10.1002/hbm.22008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. 2001. What evolution is. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLure, R. 2005. The philosophy of time. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Münsterberg, H. 1909. On the witness stand: Essays on psychology and crime. New York: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nairine, J.S. 2010. Adaptive memory: Evolutionary constraints on remembering. In The psychology of learning and motivation, Vol. 53, ed. B.H. Ross, 1–32. London: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nairne, J.S. 2005. The functionalist agenda in memory research. In Experimental cognitive psychology and its applications: A Festschrift in honor of Lyle Bourne, Walter Kintsch and Thomas Landaur, ed. A.F. Healy, 115–126. Washington DC: American Psychological Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neisser, U. 1981. John Dean’s memory: A case study. Cognition 9: 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nigro, G., and U. Neisser. 1983. Point of view in personal memories. Cognitive Psychology 15: 467–482.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penfield, W. 1952. Memory mechanisms. AMA Archives of Neurology & Psychiatry 67: 178–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Puff, C.R. 1982. Handbook of research methods in human memory and cognition. New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reid, T. 1813/1969. Essays on the intellectual powers of man. Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Renoult, L., P.S.R. Davidson, D.J. Palombo, M. Moscovitch, and B. Levince. 2012. Personal semantics: At the crossroads of semantic and episodic memory. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 16(11): 550–558.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roediger, H.L. 1996. Memory illusions. Journal of Memory and Language 35: 76–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubin, D.C. 1995. Memory in oral traditions: The cognitive psychology of epic, ballads, and counting-out rhymes. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. 1921. The analysis of mind. London: George Allen and Unwin, Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salaman, E. 1970. A collection of moments: A study of involuntary memory. New York: St. Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sani, F. 2008. Self continuity: Individual and collective perspectives. New York: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schacter, D.L. 1995. Memory distortion. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Schacter, D.L. 2012. Adaptive constructive processes and the future of memory. American Psychologist 67: 603–613.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schacter, D.L., K.A. Norman, and W. Koutstaal. 1998. The cognitive neuroscience of constructive memory. Annual Review of Psychology 49: 289–318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schacter, D.L., S.A. Guerin, and P.L. St. Jacques. 2011. Memory distortion: An adaptive perspective. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 15: 467–474.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiller, D., M. Monfils, C.M. Raio, D. Johnson, J.E. LeDoux, and E.A. Phelps. 2010. Blocking the return of fear in humans using reconsolidation update mechanisms. Nature 463: 49–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schimek, J.G. 1987. Fact and fantasy in the seduction theory: A historical review. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association 35: 937–965.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, D.J. 2004. The psychology of stereotyping. New York: The Guildford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schooler, J.W., D. Gerhard, and E.F. Loftus. 1986. Qualities of the unreal. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 12: 171–181.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwarz, N., H. Bless, F. Strack, G. Klumpp, H. Rittenauer-Schatka, and A. Simons. 1991. Ease of retrieval as information: Another look at the availability heuristic. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 61: 195–202.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellers, P.D., and B.L. Schwartz. 2013. Episodic-like animals, functional faces, and a defense of accuracy. Journal of Applied Research in Memory and Cognition 4(2): 243–245.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sherry, D.F., and D.L. Schacter. 1987. The evolution of multiple memory systems. Psychological Review 94: 439–454.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorabji, R. 1972. Aristotle on memory. Providence: Brown University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suddendorf, T., and M.C. Corballis. 1997. Mental time travel and the evolution of the human mind. Genetic, Social, and General Psychology Monographs 123: 133–167.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suddendorf, T., and M.C. Corballis. 2007. The evolution of foresight: What is mental time travel, and is it unique to humans? Behavioral and Brains Sciences 30: 299–313.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suddendorf, T., D.R. Addis, and M.C. Corbaillis. 2009. Mental time travel and the shaping of the mind. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 364: 1317–1324.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szpunar, K.K. 2010. Episodic future thought: An emerging concept. Perspectives on Psychological Science 5: 142–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Talland, G.A. 1964. Self-reference: A neglected component in remembering. American Psychologist 19: 351–353.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E. 1972. Episodic and semantic memory. In Organization of memory, ed. E. Tulving and W. Donaldson, 381–403. New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E. 1985. Memory and consciousness. Canadian Psychology/Psychologie Canadienne 26: 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E. 2005. Episodic memory and autonoesis: Uniquely human? In The missing link in cognition: Origins of self-reflective consciousness, ed. H.S. Terrace and J. Metcalfe, 3–56. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E., and F.I.M. Craik. 2000. The Oxford handbook of memory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Urmson, J.O. 1967. Memory and imagination. Mind 76: 83–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vandekerckhove, M., and P. Panksepp. 2009. The flow of anoetic to noetic and autonoetic consciousness: A vision of unknowing (anoetic) and knowing (noetic) consciousness in the remembrance of things past and imagined futures. Consciousness and Cognition 18: 1018–1028.

    Google Scholar 

  • Von Leyden, W. 1961. Remembering: A philosophical problem. New York: Philosophical Library, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warnock, M. 1987. Memory. Boston: Faber and Faber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M.A., D.T. Stuss, and E. Tulving. 1997. Toward a theory of episodic memory: The frontal lobes and autonoetic consciousness. Psychological Bulletin 121: 331–354.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, G.C. 1966. Adaptation and natural selection: A critique of some current evolutionary thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, J.Z. 1976. The evolution of memory. Burlington: Carolina Biological Supply Company, Scientific Publication Division.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stanley B. Klein.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Klein, S.B. Autonoesis and Belief in a Personal Past: An Evolutionary Theory of Episodic Memory Indices. Rev.Phil.Psych. 5, 427–447 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-014-0181-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-014-0181-8

Keywords

Navigation