Skip to main content
Log in

Explanatory Perspectivalism: Limiting the Scope of the Hard Problem of Consciousness

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I argue that the hard problem of consciousness occurs only in very limited contexts. My argument is based on the idea of explanatory perspectivalism, according to which what we want to know about a phenomenon determines the type of explanation we use to understand it. To that effect the hard problem arises only in regard to questions such as how is it that concepts of subjective experience can refer to physical properties, but not concerning questions such as what gives rise to qualia or why certain brain states have certain qualities and not others. In this sense we could for example fully explain why certain brain processes have certain subjective qualities, while we still don’t have a viable theory of concepts that explains co-referentiality of phenomenal and physical concepts. Given this limitation, the hard problem doesn’t pose a problem for the empirical study of consciousness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For more details on the Canberra plan style of conceptual analysis, see (Jackson 1998) and (Chalmers and Jackson 2001).

  2. The creatures who are functionally, structurally, behaviorally indistinguishable from us humans, but who unlike us do not have subjective conscious experiences.

  3. I’d like to thank Peter Machamer for introducing a very similar notion of investigator perspectivalism to me in the context of philosophy of experimentation.

  4. Realization and supervenience are relations that hold between properties in the world, they are not explanations themselves, but explanations based on these relations normally explain by showing how the realization and supervenience bases are individuated.

  5. This is a historical toy example. “C-fibre firing” stands for whatever actual neural mechanism of pain is. It is used as an analogy of the identity of macro concept of “water” and microphysical description “H2O”. In this toy example with qualia, the concept “pain” is a macro concept and “C-fibre firing” represents a microphysical description.

  6. Assuming for the sake of discussion that it is true that physical processes indeed give rise to qualia.

References

  • Anderson JS et al (2010) Topographic maps of multisensory attention. Proc Natl Acad Sci 107(46):20110–20114

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Basar et al (2000) Brain oscillations in perception and memory. Int J Psychophysiol 35:95–124

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bassett DS, Bullmore E (2006) Small-world brain networks. Neuroscientist 12(6):512–523

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block N, Stalnaker R (1999) Conceptual analysis, dualism, and the explanatory gap. Philos Rev 108(1):1–46

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Büchel C, Friston KJ (1997) Modulation of connectivity in visual pathways by attention: cortical interactions evaluated with structural equation modelling and fMRI. Cereb Cortex 7(8):768–778

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bullmore E, Sporns O (2009) Complex brain networks: graph theoretical analysis of structural and functional systems. Nat Rev Neurosci 10:186–198

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers D (1995) Facing up to the problem of consciousness. J Conscious Stud 2(3):200–219

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers D (1996) The conscious mind. OUP, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers D (2003) Consciousness and its place in nature. In: Stich S, Warfield F (eds) Blackwell guide to the philosophy of mind. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers D (2010) The two-dimensional argument against materialism. In: McLaughlin BP, Walter S (eds) Oxford handbook to the philosophy of mind. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers DJ (2012) Comments on Disolving the hard problem of consciousness by Glenn Carruthers and Liz Schier, Fourth Online Consciousness Conference, http://consciousnessonline.com/2012/02/17/dissolving-the-hard-problem-of-consciousness/

  • Chalmers D, Jackson J (2001) Conceptual analysis and reductive explanation. Philos Rev 110:315–360

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corbetta M, Akbudak E, Conturo TE, Snyder AZ, Ollinger JM, Drury HA, Linenweber MR, Petersen SE, Raichle ME, Van Essen DC, Shulman GL (1998) A common network of functional areas for attention and eye movements. Neuron 21(4):761–773

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowell J (2008) A priori entailment and conceptual analysis: making room for type-C physicalism. Australas J Philos 86:93–111

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eytan D, Marom S (2006) Dynamics and effective topology underlying synchronization in networks of cortical neurons. J Neurosci 26(33):8465–8476

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fortunato S (2010) Community detection in graphs. Phys Rep 486(3–5):75–174

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grossberg S (1999) The link between brain learning, attention, and consciousness. Conscious Cogn 8(1):1–44

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grossberg S (2007) Consciousness CLEARS the mind. Neural Netw 20(9):1040–1053

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • He Y, Zhang JC, Evans AC (2007) Small-world anatomical networks in the human brain revealed by cortical thickness from MRI. Cereb Cortex 17(10):2407–2419

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huneman P (2010) Topological explanations and robustness in biological sciences. Synthese 177(2):213–245

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson F (1982) Epiphenomenal Qualia. Philos Q 32(127):127–136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson F (1986) What mary didn’t know. J Philos 83(5):291–295

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson F (1998) From metaphysics to ethics: a defence of conceptual analysis. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaiser M (2011) A tutorial in connectome analysis: topological and spatial features of brain networks. NeuroImage 57(3):892–907

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim D (2004) A spiking neuron model for synchronous flashing of fireflies. Biosystems 76(1):7–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kostic D (2014a) Does network analysis provide a novel kind of topological explanations in life and brain sciences, manuscript (proceedings of the PSA 2014 in Philosophy of Science)

  • Kostic D (2014b) Topological realization, manuscript (contribution for the special issue in Synthese “Mechanistic and Topological Explanations”)

  • LaBar KS, Gitelman DR, Parrish TB, Mesulam MM (1999) Neuroanatomic overlap of working memory and spatial attention networks: a functional MRI comparison within subjects. NeuroImage 10(6):695–704

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine J (2001) Purple haze: the puzzle of conscious experience. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Newman M (2010) Networks: an introduction. OUP, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau D (2002) Thinking about consciousness. OUP, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau D (2007) Phenomenal and perceptual concepts. In: Alter T, Walter S (eds) Phenomenal concepts and phenomenal knowledge: New essays on consciousness and physicalism. OUP, Oxford, pp 111–144

    Google Scholar 

  • Raj A, Chen Y-h (2011) The wiring economy principle: connectivity determines anatomy in the human brain. PLoS One 6(9):e14832

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rubinov M, Sporns O (2010) Complex network measures of brain connectivity: uses and interpretations. NeuroImage 52(3):1059–1069

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seung SH (2009) Neuroscience: towards functional connectomics. Nature 471:170–172

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seung SH (2012) Connectome: how the brain’s wiring makes us who we are. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Trade, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sporns O (2012) Discovering the human connectome. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sporns O, Tononi G, Kötter R (2005) The human connectome: a structural description of the human brain. PLoS Comput Biol 1(4):e42

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar D (2005) Physicalism and phenomenal concepts. Mind Lang 20:469–494

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strogatz SH (2001) Exploring complex networks. Nature 410(6825):268–276

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am very much indebted for their tremendously helpful discussions and comments on various versions of this paper to: Philippe Huneman, Carl F. Craver, Paula Droege, Stephen Laurence, Peter Machamer, Joseph Levine, Raphael van Riel, Liz Schier and Duško Prelević. I would like to emphasize my enormous gratitude for their encouragement and support to: Paula Droege, Philippe Huneman and Carl F. Craver. My special thanks goes to Paual Giladi and Zorana Todorović for their meticulous job at proofreading the manuscript. I would also like to thank to two anonymous reviewers for their very useful comments that helped me greatly improve this paper. The research in this paper is done within the project Dynamical Systems in Nature and Society: Philosophical and Empirical Aspects (project number: 179051) which is supported by the Ministry of Education, Science and Technological Development of the Republic of Serbia.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel Kostić.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kostić, D. Explanatory Perspectivalism: Limiting the Scope of the Hard Problem of Consciousness. Topoi 36, 119–125 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-014-9262-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-014-9262-7

Keywords

Navigation