Skip to main content
Log in

Proof-Theoretic Semantics, a Problem with Negation and Prospects for Modality

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper discusses proof-theoretic semantics, the project of specifying the meanings of the logical constants in terms of rules of inference governing them. I concentrate on Michael Dummett’s and Dag Prawitz’ philosophical motivations and give precise characterisations of the crucial notions of harmony and stability, placed in the context of proving normalisation results in systems of natural deduction. I point out a problem for defining the meaning of negation in this framework and prospects for an account of the meanings of modal operators in terms of rules of inference.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. [2228] is a representative selection of Prawitz’ papers.

  2. This is an interesting omission: in the systems of Gentzen [16], structural rules are as natural a part of natural deduction as inference rules.

  3. It is sometimes said that there are inconsistent, i.e. non-conservative, connectives that have stable rules. This is impossible on the account of next section: in a logic with only stable rules, neither ⊥ nor an arbitrary atomic proposition is provable. A version of Dummett’s conjecture also holds, but it has to be said that it is not the most interesting result.

  4. There are similarities to the view that logic is ‘topic neutral’ or ‘carries no information’.

  5. Prior [32]. Belnap [1] suggests that logical constants need to be conservative, but Prior was not convinced this is sufficient [33].

  6. See Francez and Dyckhoff [13] and Read [36] and literature referred to there.

  7. In an intuitionist modal logic where both □ and ♢ are present, the restrictions may have to be more complicated. For the classical case, we can assume that the logic only has □.

  8. I’m using this restriction as it mirrors the rules of Biermann and de Paiva [2] in the next section. An intuitionist modal logic may require more complicated restrictions, such as those of Prawitz [21].

  9. Besides the works already cited, Dummett’s [5, 6, 9] and [10] contain extensive discussions of the issue.

  10. There are several proposals for how to formulate classical logic in a such a way that its rules may count as harmonious, e.g., Milne [19] and Read [34]. It is fair to say that they all deviate in some way from Dummett’s and Prawitz’ harmony.

  11. Or □A, in modal logic. A local peak with □E after ⊥ E can be levelled.

  12. This argument can be found in Hand [18], but it has probably occurred to many philosophers independently, amongst them the present author.

  13. Tennant [42], which is a response to Hand [18].

  14. Brandom ([3]: Lecture 5, p.8ff). His definition of negation is different from Tennant’s, but there is no need to go into the details here. A similar approach can already be found in Demos [4]. It never really caught on, maybe because of Russell’s criticism ([40]: 5ff), ([41]: 211ff).

  15. See Price [2931]. Rumfitt [37] develops a formal framework for the account, which has sparked some discussion. See [11, 12, 17, 38, 39]. Textor [43] is a critical assessment of whether there is a speech act of denial that is prior to the assertion of negated sentences. It is worth adding that according to Tennant and Rumfitt, ⊥ isn’t a proposition, but a ‘structural punctuation mark’. Nonetheless, it plays a role in their calculi that can be played by a proposition or speech act. Despite their declarations, someone who is being taught the rules of their calculi may not come to the conclusion that ⊥ is quite so special, and I’m not convinced that would just be a confusion.

  16. Modal notions are almost never discussed in Dummett/Prawitz-style proof-theoretic semantics. Read [35] uses a labelled deductive system, which strikes me as possible worlds semantics dressed up. Pfenning and Davies [20] is closer to what I say here.

References

  1. Belnap, N. (1962). Tonk, plonk and blink. Analysis, 22, 130–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Biermann, G. M., & de Paiva, V. CV. (2000). On an intuitionistic modal logic. Studia Logica, 65, 383–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Brandom, R. (2006). The John Locke lectures. http://www.pitt.edu/brandom/locke/index.html Accessed 08 Nov 2013.

  4. Demos, R. (1917). A discussion of a certain type of negative propositions. Mind, 26, 188–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Dummett, M. (1978a). The justification of deduction. In Truth and other enigmas (pp. 290–318). London: Duckworth.

  6. Dummett, M. (1978b). The philosophical basis of intuitionistic logic. In Truth and other enigmas (pp. 215–247). London: Duckworth.

  7. Dummett, M. (1981). Frege. Philosophy of language, 2nd edn. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Dummett, M. (1993a). The logical basis of metaphysics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  9. Dummett, M. (1993b). What is a theory of meaning? (I). In The seas of language (pp. 1–33). Oxford: Clarendon.

  10. Dummett, M. (1993c). What is a theory of meaning? (II). In The seas of language (pp. 34–93). Oxford: Clarendon.

  11. Dummett, M. (2002). “Yes”, “No” and “Can’t Say”. Mind 111, 289–295.

  12. Ferreira, F. (2008). The co-ordination principles: a problem for bilateralism. Mind, 117, 1051–1057.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Francez, N., & Dyckhoff, R. (2012). A note on harmony. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 41, 613–628.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Frege, G. (1990). Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik. Hildesheim, Zürich, New York: Olms.

  15. Gentzen, G. (1934). Untersuchungen über das logische Schließen. Mathematische Zeitschrift, 39(176–210), 405–431.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Gentzen, G. (1935). Die Widerspruchsfreiheit der reinen Zahlentheorie. Mathematische Annalen, 112, 493–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Gibbard, P. (2002). Price and Rumfitt on rejective negation and classical logic. Mind, 111, 297–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Hand, M. (1999). Anti-realism and falsity. In D. Gabbay & H. Wansing (Eds.), What is negation? (pp. 185–198). Dortrecht: Kluwer.

  19. Milne, P. (1994). Classical harmony: rules of inference and the meanings of the logical constants. Synthese, 100, 49–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Pfenning, F., & Davies, R. (2001). A judgemental reconstruction of modal logic. Mathematical Structures in Computer Science, 11, 511–540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Prawitz, D. (1965). Natural deduction. Stockholm: Almqvist and Wiksell.

  22. Prawitz, D. (1974). On the idea of a general proof-theory. Synthese, 27, 63–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Prawitz, D. (1979). Proofs and the meaning and completeness of the logical constants. In J.H. et al. (Ed.), Essays on mathematical and philosophical logic (pp. 25–40). Dordrecht: Reidel.

  24. Prawitz, D. (1987). Dummett on a theory of meaning and its impact on logic. In B. Taylor (Ed.), Michael Dummett: contributions to philosophy (pp. 117–165). Dordrecht: Nijhoff.

  25. Prawitz, D. (1994a). Meaning theory and anti-realism. In B. McGuiness (Ed.), The philosophy of Michael Dummett (pp. 79–89). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  26. Prawitz, D. (1994b). Review of the logical basis of metaphysics. Mind, 103, 373–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Prawitz, D. (2006). Meaning approached via proofs. Synthese, 148, 507–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Prawitz, D. (2007). Pragmatist and verificationist theories of meaning. In R. Auxier & L. Hahn (Eds.), The philosophy of Michael Dummett (pp. 455–481). Chicago: Open Court.

  29. Price, H. (1983). Sense, assertion, Dummett and denial. Mind, 92, 161–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Price, H. (1990). Why ‘not’? Mind, 99, 221–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Price, H. (2010). ‘Not’ again. http://prce.hu/w/preprints/NotAgain.pdf. Accessed 08 Nov 2013.

  32. Prior, A. (1961). The runabout inference ticket. Analysis, 21, 38–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Prior, A. (1964). Conjunction and contonktion revisited. Analysis, 24, 191–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Read, S. (2000). Harmony and autonomy in classical logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 29, 123–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Read, S. (2008). Harmony and modality. In L.K.C. Dégremont & H. Rückert (Eds.), Dialogues, logics and other strange things: essays in Honour of Shahid Rahman (pp. 285–303). London: College Publications.

  36. Read, S. (2010). General-elimination harmony and the meaning of the logical constants. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 39, 557–576.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Rumfitt, I. (2000). “Yes” and “No”. Mind, 109, 781–823.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Rumfitt, I. (2002). Unilateralism disarmed: a reply to Dummett and Gibbard. Mind, 111, 305–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Rumfitt, I. (2008). Co-ordination principles: a reply. Mind, 117, 1059–1063.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Russell, B. (1919). On propositions: what they are and how they mean. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian society (Vol. 2, pp. 1–43).

  41. Russell, B. (1956). The philosophy of logical atomism. In Logic and knowledge, essays 1901–1950 (pp. 175–283). Routledge.

  42. Tennant, N. (1999). Negation, absurdity and contrariety. In D. Gabbay & H. Wansing (Eds.), What is negation? (pp. 199–222). Dortrecht: Kluwer.

  43. Textor, M. (2011). Is ‘no’ a force indicator? No!. Analysis, 71(3), 448–456.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Anneli Jefferson, Jessica Leech and Julien Murzi for their very helpful comments on this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nils Kürbis.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kürbis, N. Proof-Theoretic Semantics, a Problem with Negation and Prospects for Modality. J Philos Logic 44, 713–727 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-013-9310-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-013-9310-6

Keywords

Navigation