Skip to main content
Log in

Aristotelian motivational externalism

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recent virtue theorists in psychology implicitly assume the truth of motivational internalism, and this assumption restricts the force and scope of the message that they venture to offer as scientists. I aim to contrive a way out of their impasse by arguing for a version of Aristotelian motivational externalism and suggesting why these psychologists should adopt it. There is a more general problem, however. Although motivational externalism has strong intuitive appeal, at least for moral realists and ‘Humeans’ about motivation, it continues to be threatened by Smith’s fetishisation argument and burdened by the inability of its familiar counter-examples to internalism (of the immoral, wicked, listless and amoral persons) to bear full scrutiny. I argue that Aristotle’s example of the continent person (as distinct from the fully virtuous) offers a more persuasive counter-example to internalism. The moral judgements of continent persons do not motivate them intrinsically, yet the continent cannot be counted as practically irrational with regard to morality. If Aristotelian motivational externalism holds true, psychologists can offer full-fledged theories of virtue without the danger of turning the science of psychology into a prescriptive moralism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There are at least two importantly different formulations of this caveat in the literature: one includes ‘practical irrationality’; the other only ‘general motivational disorder’. As I propose to present motivational internalism in its least controversial and most plausible form, I include both.

  2. By ‘intrinsically’ here I mean ‘non-derivatively’ and ‘non-instrumentally’. I do not mean to beg questions against Humean motivational internalists, such as Smith (1994), who do not believe that judgements motivate on their own (but rather through an intrinsic connection to a desire that triggers motivation).

  3. I mean here ‘moral rightness’, not ‘rightness all things considered’.

  4. It should be noted that while openly embracing moral cognitivism, Svavarsdóttir does not seem to have committed explicitly one way or another on the realist issue.

  5. It is in order to mention briefly here the difference between motivational externalism and reason externalism (although I shall leave the latter out of further reckoning in what follows). For the reason externalist, moral judgement does not commit the agent making it to the recognition of the reason-giving force of the judgement. I consider that to be an unfounded claim. Surely a moral judgement about, say, the moral goodness of helping a blind person across the street, provides for any rational agent a recognisable reason for action. Hence, I would add to Railton’s admission the point that all sane motivational externalists will endorse reason internalism (about a necessary connection between moral judgement and the recognition of a justifying reason for action), while insisting on the assumption that the recognition of a justifying reason does not, any more than moral judgement, necessarily carry motivational force (cf. Mason 2008, p. 139).

  6. For a misguided non-Humean interpretation of Aristotle, see McDowell (1978, 1979).

  7. McDowell (1978, 1979) has also argued that the virtuous and the continent are not making the same kind of moral judgement. His elucidation of this claim (and his interpretation of Aristotle) differs from mine in several respects, however. McDowell suggests that whereas the virtuous person’s judgement that a situation demands a certain action constitutes a motivating belief, the continent person’s judgement that a situation demands a certain action is a belief accompanied by a separate desire. I think that the correct Aristotelian position is that no beliefs can motivate on their own (see footnote 6 above). McDowell understands the judgement of the virtuous in perceptual, intuitivist and particularist terms: as spontaneous, ‘unclouded’, situation-specific sensitivity (see esp. 1979, p. 334). I understand it in cognitivist, theory-laden and generalist terms. The difference between the judgements of the virtuous and continent does not lie in the difference between unclouded and clouded vision but in other factors, as I explain in the following paragraph. McDowell takes the moral judgements of the virtuous to be essentially uncodifiable (1979, p. 336). I have argued, in contrast, that such moral judgements are not essentially uncodifiable although they are, more often than not, factually uncodifiable (see Kristjánsson 2007, Chap. 11).

  8. Incidentally, I do not think that what has come to be known as the ‘Humean’ notion of practical rationality is actually Hume’s true notion; I agree with Karlsson (2006) that Hume’s view is similar to Aristotle’s, and also makes room for cognitive errors of irrationality about ends.

  9. For this reading of Foot’s change of mind, compare Foot (1972, p. 310) about the non-‘reason-giving force’ of moral judgements with the ‘intrinsic link’ she explains in 2001 between goodness and ‘reasons for action’ (2001, p. 64).

  10. Incidentally, the positive psychologists in question do not seem to realise that, according to motivational internalism, specific moral judgements about the moral good of particular virtues or of particular pathways to happiness entail (on a motivational understanding of prescriptivity) a moral prescription no less than overall moral judgements. Given their internalist assumption, the positive psychologists thus seem to have violated Hume’s is–ought distinction, as they understand it, even with their reserved moral stance of refraining from advancing a fully developed theory of virtue.

References

  • Allport, G. W. (1937). Personality: A psychological interpretation. New York: Holt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1985). Nicomachean ethics (Irwin, Trans.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

  • Benn, S. (1985). Wickedness. Ethics, 95(3), 795–810.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brickhouse, T. C. (1991). Roberts on responsibility for action and character in the Nicomachean ethics. Ancient Philosophy, 11(1), 137–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brink, D. O. (1997). Moral motivation. Ethics, 108(4), 4–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brinkmann, S. (2011). Psychology as a moral science: Perspectives on normativity. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cholbi, M. (2011). Depression, listlessness, and moral motivation. Ratio (New Series), 24(1), 28–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Curzer, H. J. (2005). How good people do bad things: Aristotle on the misdeeds of the virtuous. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 28(1), 233–256.

    Google Scholar 

  • Falk, W. D. (1948). ‘Ought’ and motivation. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 48, 492–510.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, O. (1991). Varieties of moral personality: Ethics and psychological realism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (1972). Morality as a system of hypothetical imperatives. Philosophical Review, 81(3), 305–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (2001). Natural goodness. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Francén, R. (2010). Moral motivation pluralism. Journal of Ethics, 14(1), 117–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldie, P. (2009). Thick concepts and emotion. In D. Callcut (Ed.), Reading Bernard Williams (pp. 94–110). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goleman, D. (1995). Emotional intelligence. New York: Bantam Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1978). A treatise of human nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Inwood, B. (1985). Ethics and human action in early Stoicism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karlsson, M. M. (2006). Reason, passion, and the influencing motives of the will. In S. Traiger (Ed.), The Blackwell guide to Hume’s treatise (pp. 235–255). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kohlberg, L. (1981). Essays on moral development, vol. 1: The philosophy of moral development. San Francisco: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krehbiel, P. J., & Cropanzano, R. (2000). Procedural justice, outcome favorability, and emotion. Social Justice Research, 15(4), 339–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kristjánsson, K. (2006). Justice and desert-based emotions. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kristjánsson, K. (2007). Aristotle, emotions, and education. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kristjánsson, K. (2010a). The self and its emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kristjánsson, K. (2010b). Positive psychology, happiness, and virtue: The troublesome conceptual issues. Review of General Psychology, 14(4), 296–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kristjánsson, K. (2010c). Emotion education without ontological commitment? Studies in Philosophy and Education, 29(3), 259–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kristjánsson, K. (2010d). The trouble with ambivalent emotions. Philosophy, 85(4), 485–510.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lapsley, D., & Narvaez, D. (2008). ‘Psychologized morality’ and its discontents, or, do good fences make good neighbours? In F. Oser & W. Veugelers (Eds.), Getting involved: Global citizenship development and sources of moral value (pp. 279–292). Rotterdam: Sense Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenman, J. (1999). The externalist and the amoralist. Philosophia, 27(3–4), 441–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mason, E. (2008). An argument against motivational internalism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 108(2), 135–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1978). Are moral requirements hypothetical imperatives? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume, 52, 13–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1979). Virtue and reason. The Monist, 62(3), 331–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. R. (1996). Internalist moral cognitivism and listlessness. Ethics, 106(3), 727–753.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, C. B. (2008). Motivational internalism. Philosophical Studies, 139(2), 233–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, A. W. (2006). Maxims and thick ethical concepts. Ratio (New Series), 19(2), 129–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, C., & Seligman, M. E. P. (2004). Character strengths and virtues: A handbook and classification. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Railton, P. (1986). Moral realism. Philosophical Review, 95(2), 163–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Railton, P. (2009). Internalism for externalists. Philosophical Issues, 19, 166–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seligman, M. E. P. (2011). Flourish: A visionary new understanding of happiness and well-being. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sihvola, J. (2004). Aristotle and modern moral realism. Acta Philosophica Fennica, 76, 201–229.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1994). The moral problem. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stocker, M. (1979). Desiring the bad: An essay in moral psychology. Journal of Philosophy, 76(12), 738–753.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strandberg, C. (2000). Aristotle’s internalism in the Nicomachean ethics. Journal of Value Inquiry, 34(1), 71–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Svavarsdóttir, S. (1999). Moral cognitivism and motivation. Philosophical Review, 108(2), 161–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Svavarsdóttir, S. (2005). How do moral judgments motivate? In J. Dreier (Ed.), Contemporary debates in moral theory (pp. 163–181). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Svavarsdóttir, S. (2009). The practical role essential to value judgments. Philosophical Issues, 19, 299–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1973). Problems of the self. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1982). Moral luck. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1965). A lecture on ethics. Philosophical Review, 74(1), 3–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zangwill, N. (2003). Externalist moral motivation. American Philosophical Quarterly, 40(2), 143–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zangwill, N. (2008). The indifference argument. Philosophical Studies, 138(1), 91–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgment

I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer of the present journal for extended and particularly helpful comments on earlier versions of this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kristján Kristjánsson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kristjánsson, K. Aristotelian motivational externalism. Philos Stud 164, 419–442 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9863-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9863-1

Keywords

Navigation