Skip to main content
Log in

Consciousness, Higher-Order Content, and the Individuation of Vehicles

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

One of the distinctive properties of conscious states is thepeculiar self-awareness implicit in them. Two rival accounts of this self-awareness are discussed. Accordingto a Neo-Brentanian account, a mental state M is conscious iff M represents its very own occurrence.According to the Higher-Order Monitoring account, M is merely accompanied by a numerically distinctrepresentation of its occurrence. According to both, then, M is conscious in virtue of figuring in a higher-ordercontent. The disagreement is over the question whether the higher-order content is carried by Mitself or by a different state. While theNeo-Brentanian theory is phenomenologically more attractive, it isoften felt to be somewhat mysterious. It is argued (i) that the difference between the Neo-Brentanian andHigher-Order Monitoring theories is smaller and more empirical than may initially seem, and (ii) that theNeo-Brentanian theory can be readily demystified. These considerations make it prima faciepreferable to the Higher-Order Monitoring theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

REFERENCES

  • Anscombe, G. E. M.: 1957, Intention, Blackwell, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. M.: 1968, A Materialist Theory of the Mind, Humanities Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. M.: 1981, 'What is Consciousness?', The Nature of Mind 55-67; Reprinted in Block et al. (1997).

  • Block, N. J.: 1995, 'On a Confusion about the Function of Consciousness', Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18, 227–247; Reprinted in Block et al. (1997).

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. J., O. Flanagan, and G. Guzeldere (eds.): 1997, The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates, MIT/Bradford, Cambridge MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F.: 1874, In O. Kraus (ed.), Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint, English edition. L. L. McAlister, trans. A. C. Rancurello, D. B. Terrell, and L. L. McAlister, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London (1973).

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, D.: 1996, 'Some Like it HOT: Consciousness and Higher Order Thoughts', Philosophical Studies 86, 103–129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P.: 2000, Phenomenal Consciousness, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda, H.-N.: 1966, ' “He”: A Study in the Logic of Self-Consciousness', Ratio 8, 130–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda, H.-N.: 1969, 'On the Phenomeno-Logic of the I', Proceedings of the 14th International Congress of Philosophy iii; Reprinted in Q. Cassam (ed.), Self-Knowledge, Oxford University Press (1994).

  • Caston, V.: 2002, 'Aristotle on Consciousness', Mind, forthcoming.

  • Chalmers, D.: 1995, 'Facing Up to the Problem of Consciousness', Journal of Consciousness Studies 2, 200–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crick, F. and C. Koch: 1990, 'Towards a Neurobiological Theory of Consciousness', Seminars in the Neurosciences 2, 263–275, Reprinted in Block et al. (1997).

    Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J.: 1993, Moral Reasons, Blackwell, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C.: 1969, Consciousness and Content, Routledge, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C.: 1987, The Intentional Stance, MIT/Bradford, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. I.: 1981, Knowledge and the Flow of Information, Clarendon, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. I.: 1988, Explaining Behavior, MIT/Bradford, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engel, A. K., P. Fries, P. Konig, M. Brecht, and W. Singer 1999, 'Temporal Binding, Binocular Rivalry, and Consciousness', Consciousness and Cognition 8, 128–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. G.: 1971, 'Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person', Journal of Philosophy 68, 5–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gennaro, R. J.: 1996, Consciousness and Self-Consciousness, John Benjamin Publishing Co., Philadelphia/Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A.: 1970, A Theory of Human Action, Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A.: 1993, 'Consciousness, Folk Psychology, and Cognitive Science', Consciousness and Cognition 2, 364–383; Reprinted in Block et al. (1997).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, R. M.: 1987, The Structure of Emotion, MIT Press/Bradford Books, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E.: 1928, In M. Heidegger (ed.), Phenomenology of Internal Time-Consciousness, J. S. Churchill (trans.), Indiana University Press, Bloomington, IN (1964).

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W.: 1892, In G. Allport (ed.), Psychology: The Briefer Course, Harper and Row, New York (1961).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U.: 2002, 'Consciousness, Permanent Self-Awareness, and Higher Order Monitoring', Dialogue, forthcoming.

  • Kripke, S.: 1980, 'The Identity Thesis', in his Naming and Necessity; Reprinted in Block et al. (1997).

  • Little, M. O.: 1997, 'Virtue as Knowledge: Objections from the Philosophy of Mind', Nous 31, 59–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. G.: 1990, 'Consciousness as Internal Monitoring', Philosophical Perspectives 9, 1–14; Reprinted in Block et al. (1997).

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. G.: 1996, Consciousness and Experience, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. G.: 2001, 'A Simple Argument for a Higher-Order Representation Theory of Consciousness', Analysis 61, 3–4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, G. W. and S. E. Boer: 1975, 'Knowing Who', Philosophical Studies 28, 299–344.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J.: 1979, 'Virtue and Reason', Monist 62, 331–350.

    Google Scholar 

  • McNaughton, D.: 1988, Moral Vision, Blackwell, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • von der Malsburg, C.: 1981, 'The Correlation Theory of Brain Function', Technical Report 81-2, Max-Planck-Institute for Biophysical Chemistry, Gottingen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger, T.: 1995, 'Faster than Thought: Holism, Homogeneity, and Temporal Coding', in T. Metzinger (ed.), Conscious Experience, Inprint Academic, Thorverton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G.: 1984, Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories, MIT, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T.: 1974, 'What is it Like to Be a Bat', Philosophical Review 83, 435–450; Reprinted in Block et al. (1997).

    Google Scholar 

  • Revonsuo, A.: 1999, 'Binding and the Phenomenal Unity of Consciousness', in Consciousness and Cognition 8, 173–185.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rey, G.: 1988, 'A Question about Consciousness', in H. Otto and J. Tueidio (eds.), Perspectives on Mind, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Norwell; Reprinted in Block et al. (1997).

    Google Scholar 

  • Roelfsema, P. R., A. K. Engel, P. Konig, and W. Singer: 1997, 'Visuomotor Integration is Associated with Zero Time-Lag Synchronization among Cortical Areas', Nature 385, 157–161.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. M.: 1986, 'Two Concepts of Consciousness', Philosophical Studies 94, 329–359; Reprinted in D. M. Rosenthal (ed.), The Nature of Mind, Oxford University Press, New York and Oxford (1991).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. M.: 1990, 'A Theory of Consciousness', ZiF Technical Report 40, Bielfield, Germany; Reprinted in Block et al. (1997).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. M.: 1991, 'The Independence of Consciousness and Sensory Quality', Philosophical Issues 1, 15–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. M.: 1993, 'Thinking that One Thinks', in M. Davies and G. W. Humphreys (eds.), Consciousness: Psychological and Philosophical Essays, Blackwell, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, D. M.: 2002, Mind and Consciousness, Oxford University Press, Oxford, forthcoming.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P.: 1937, The Transcendence of the Ego, F. Williams and R. Kirkpatrick (trans.), Noonday Press, New York (1957).

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R.: 1983, Intentionality, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, W.: 1994, 'The Organization of Sensory Motor Representations in the Neocortex: A Hypothesis Based on Temporal Coding', in C. Umilta and M. Moscovitch (eds.), Attention and Performance XV: Conscious and Nonconscious Information Processing, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, D. W.: 1986, 'The Structure of (Self-)Consciousness', Topoi 5, 149–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M.: 1987, 'The Humean Theory of Motivation', Mind 96, 36–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. L.: 2000, 'After Brentano: A One-Level Theory of Consciousness', European Journal of Philosophy 8, 190–209.

    Google Scholar 

  • Treisman, A. M. and H. Schmidt: 1982, 'Illusory Conjunctions in the Perception of Objects', Cognitive Psychology 14, 107–141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Gulick, R.: 1988, 'A Functionalist Plea for Self-Consciousness', Philosophical Review 97, 149–181.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Gulick, R.: 2001, 'Inward and Upward-Reflection, Introspection, and Self-Awareness', Philosophical Topics 28, 275–305.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D.: 1999, Self-Awareness and Alterity, Northwestern University Press, Evanston, IL.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zeki, S., J. D. G. Watson, C. J. Lueck, K. J. Friston, C. Kennard, and R. S. J. Frackowiak: 1991, 'A Direct Demonstration of Functional Specialization in Human Visual Cortex', Journal of Neuroscience 11, 641–649.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kriegel, U. Consciousness, Higher-Order Content, and the Individuation of Vehicles. Synthese 134, 477–504 (2003). https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1022913321854

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1022913321854

Keywords

Navigation