Skip to main content
Log in

Contrastive statistical explanation and causal heterogeneity

  • Original paper in Philosophy of Science
  • Published:
European Journal for Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Probabilistic phenomena are often perceived as being problematic targets for contrastive explanation. It is usually thought that the possibility of contrastive explanation hinges on whether or not the probabilistic behaviour is irreducibly indeterministic, and that the possible remaining contrastive explananda are token event probabilities or complete probability distributions over such token outcomes. This paper uses the invariance-under-interventions account of contrastive explanation to argue against both ideas. First, the problem of contrastive explanation also arises in cases in which the probabilistic behaviour of the explanandum is due to unobserved causal heterogeneity. Second, it turns out that, in contrast to the case of pure indeterminism, the plausible contrastive explananda under causal heterogeneity are not token event probabilities, but population-level statistical facts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Percival (2000) makes a distinction between strongly chancy events that have a non-trivial objective probability of occurring for all times in their causal history, and weakly chancy events that are truly chancy only for some parts of their causal history. This distinction is rarely, if ever, empirically determinable and therefore cannot be used to solve the problem of contrastive explanation under indeterminism.

  2. The fact that Hempel had to resort to the requirement of maximal specificity to deal with the problems of ambiguity and epistemic relativity (see, e.g., Niiniluoto 2000) should be seen as an argument against the broader Hempelian framework, not as an argument for maximal specificity.

  3. Note that this is a non-standard way of formulating the quantum-physical problem. I have no idea whether such a function can be given a closed-form expression. In general, such functional dependencies are often harder to determine compared to the joint distribution of the variables and this difficulty may be seen as one facet of the general problematic of probabilities and contrastive explanation.

  4. do(X = x) indicates, in the usual manner, that the value of X variable was set to x by an intervention. Since this expression is here used merely to remind the reader of the intended interpretation of the conditioning event and no formal work is done with it, no rigorous definitions are offered.

  5. Granted, sometimes these kinds of counterfactual evaluations are precisely the point of causal language. For example, sometimes the heritability measure H 2 (which is just R 2 with H for heritability) is used as if to gauge the causal contribution of the genome for a trait in a population. What this purported causal factor expressing the contribution of the genome is supposed to tell us is how the traits would have developed, if we indeed had reshuffled all the environmental factors during the development. However, even this usage is usually seen as very problematic (Lewontin 1974).

  6. There are important differences in the conditions under which average treatment effects can be consistently estimated for different sub-populations. However, since these differences are not important for the philosophical points developed here, they are not discussed further.

References

  • Angrist, J., & Pischke, J.-S. (2009). Mostly harmless econometrics: An empiricist’s companion. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braumoeller, B. (2006). Explaining variance; or, stuck in a moment we can’t get out of. Political Analysis, 14, 268–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1989). Nature’s capacities and their measurement. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Downs, G. W., & Rocke, D. M. (1979). Interpreting heteroscedasticity. American Journal of Political Science, 23, 816–828.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freedman, D. (2004). On specifying graphical models for causation, and the identification problem. Evaluation Review, 26, 267–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (1979). Understanding scientific reasoning. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (1984). Causal models with frequency dependence. Journal of Philosophy, 81, 384–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glymour, B. (1998). Contrastive, non-probabilistic statistical explanations. Philosophy of Science, 65, 448–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C. (1999). Contrastive explanation and the demons of determinism. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 50, 585–612.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holland, P. (1986). Statistics and causal inference. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 81, 945–960.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holland, P. (1994). Probabilistic causation without probability. In P. Humphreys (Ed.), Patrick Suppes: Scientific philosopher, vol 1 (pp. 257–287). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Holland, P. (2001). The causal interpretation of regression coefficients. In M. C. Galavotti, P. Suppes, & D. Constantini (Eds.), Stochastic causality (pp. 173–187). Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • King, G., Keohane, R. O., & Verba, S. (1994). Designing social inquiry: Scientific inference in qualitative research. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In P. Kitcher & W. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation (pp. 410–505). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). Philosophical papers, vol. II. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R. (1974). The analysis of variance and the analysis of causes. American Journal of Human Genetics, 26, 400–411.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. (1974). The cement of the universe. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, S., & Winship, C. (2007). Counterfactuals and causal inference: Methods and principles for social research. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1981). Statistical explanation reconsidered. Synthese, 48, 437–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (2000). Hempel’s theory of statistical explanation. In J. Fetzer (Ed.), Science, explanation, and rationality: The philosophy of Carl G (pp. 138–163). Hempel: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: Models, reasoning and inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Percival, P. (2000). Lewis’s dilemma of explanation under indeterminism exposed and resolved. Mind, 109, 39–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pratt, J. W., & Schlaifer, R. (1988). On the interpretation and observation of laws. Journal of Econometrics, 39, 23–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Railton, P. (1978). A deductive-nomological model of probabilistic explanations. Philosophy of Science, 45, 206–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Railton, P. (1981). Probability, explanation and information. Synthese, 48, 233–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russo, F. (2007). Causality and causal modelling in the social sciences: Measuring variations. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1998). Causation and explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schweder, R. (2007). Some notes on unificationism and probabilistic explanation. In J. Persson & P. Ylikoski (Eds.), Rethinking explanation (pp. 119–128). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1986). Explanatory presupposition. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 64, 143–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spanos, A. (1995). On theory testing in econometrics: modeling with nonexperimental data. Journal of Economometrics, 67, 189–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steyer, R., Gabler, S., von Davier, A., Nachtigall, C., & Buhl, T. (2000). Causal regression models II: unconfoundedness and causal unbiasedness. Methods of Psychological Research Online, 5(3), 55–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2000). Do large probabilities explain better? Philosophy of Science, 67, 366–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (1980). Scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Winship, C., & Morgan, S. L. (1999). The estimation of causal effects from observational data. Annual Review of Sociology, 25, 659–706.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen—A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ylikoski, P., & Kuorikoski, J. (2010). Dissecting explanatory power. Philosophical Studies, 148, 201–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jaakko Kuorikoski.

Additional information

The author would like to thank the reviewers and the audience of the Philosophy of Science Seminar at the University of Helsinki for their valuable comments. This research has been supported by the Academy of Finland.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kuorikoski, J. Contrastive statistical explanation and causal heterogeneity. Euro Jnl Phil Sci 2, 435–452 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-012-0050-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-012-0050-1

Keywords

Navigation