Skip to main content
Log in

Locked-in Syndrome and BCI - Towards an Enactive Approach to the Self

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Neuroethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It has been argued that Extended Cognition (EXT), a recently much discussed framework in the philosophy of cognition, would serve as the theoretical basis to account for the impact of Brain Computer Interfaces (BCI) on the self and life of patients with Locked-in Syndrome (LIS). In this paper I will argue that this claim is unsubstantiated, EXT is not the appropriate theoretical background for understanding the role of BCI in LIS. I will critically assess what a theory of the extended self would comprise and provide a list of desiderata for a theory of self that EXT fails to accommodate for. There is, however, an alternative framework in Cognitive Science, Enactivism, which entails the basis for an account of self that is able to accommodate for these desiderata. I will outline some first steps towards an Enactive approach to the self, suggesting that the self could be considered as a form of human autonomy. Understanding the self from an enactive point of view will allow to shed new light on the questions of whether and how BCIs affect or change the selves of patients with LIS.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In accordance with Fenton and Alpert, as well as Walter I refer to “Extended Cognition” as the position originally put forward by Clark and Chalmers.

  2. I owe this example to Ezequiel Di Paolo.

  3. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for raising this worry.

  4. Even if we take the self to be based on cognitive processes, a claim about the nature of the vehicle of some cognitive processes would not be telling without understanding what self is, and what exactly the cognitive processes involved are.

  5. They do admit that extended cognition is in principle possible, but argue that “as a matter of contingent empirical fact” cognition takes place in the brain (pp.55,70) [23].

  6. As an anonymous reviewer has correctly pointed out, this does not rule out that it is in principle possible to combine both approaches. The crucial point is that while EXT maybe applied to the relation of BCI and LIS with respect to specific cognitive processes, ENC is a better theoretical framework to account for the self in LIS/BCI. However, given the more general problems of EXT, e.g. the lack of definition of cognition, and its widespread ignorance of the role of the subjective experience a combination of both approaches may be unwarranted after all. Furthermore, if explanatory efficiency matters, than it maybe better to not combine a framework that is explanatorily less encompassing with a second one, but opt for a single, explanatorily more fruitful framework, if such a framework is available.

  7. I propose that these social interactions of distinction and participation are by and large established by communication, which is not restricted to linguistic or verbal communication—bodily postures, touch, gestures and facial expressions etc. are included.

  8. The above considerations have at least two implications. First, the constitutive processes of distinction and participation have to be constantly realized. This is to say that human autonomy would necessarily be affected to the degree that its constitutive processes are; it might even cease to exist, when these processes are absent for a critical time. Secondly, if self is seen as coinciding with human autonomy, which is not constituted by the organism alone, but through social interactions, it cannot be innate and it is also questionable whether very young infants would have it.

  9. Note that I by no means assume that these considerations exhaustively account for the role of BCI. This would indeed require a much more thorough investigation, and is a task for future work. The purpose here is to highlight new avenues for addressing this question and rethinking the role of BCI for LIS. I have to thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this worry.

References

  1. Bauer, G., F. Gerstenbrand, and E. Rumpl. 1979. Varieties of locked-in syndrome. Journal of Neurology 221: 77–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Inci, S., and T. Özgen. 2003. Locked-in syndrome due to metastatic pontomedullary tumor—case report. Neurologia Medico-Chirurgica 43: 497–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Laureys, S. et al. 2005. The locked-in syndrome : what is it like to be conscious but paralyzed and voiceless? In Laureys, S. (Ed.). Progress in Brain Research: 150.

  4. León-Carrión, J., P. van Eeckhout, and M. Del Rosario Domínguez-Morales. 2002. The locked-in syndrome: a syndrome looking for a therapy. Brain Injury 16: 555–569.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Bauby, J.D. 1997. The diving bell and the butterfly. London: Harper Perennial.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Wolpaw, J.N., D. Birbaumer, G.P. McFarland, and T. Vaughan. 2002. Brain-computer interfaces for communication and control. Clinical Neurophysiology 113: 767–791.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Birbaumer, N., et al. 2002. Brain-computer interfaces for communication and control, in. Clinical Neurophysiology 113: 767–791.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Birbaumer, N. 2006. Breaking the silence: Brain-computer interfaces (BCI) for communication and motor control. Psychophysiology 43(6): 517–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Birbaumer, N., and L.G. Cohen. 2007. Brain–computer interfaces: communication and restoration of movement in paralysis. The Journal of Physiology 579(3): 621–636.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Kyselo, M. and Di Paolo, E. in progress. Through the enactive eye—locked-in syndrome as a challenge for embodied cognition.

  11. Kurthen, M., et al. 1991. The locked-in syndrome and the behaviorist epistemology of other minds. Theoretical Medicine 12: 69–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Dudzinski, D. 2001. The diving bell meets the butterfly: identity lost and re-membered. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 22: 33–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Fenton, A., and S. Alpert. 2008. Extending our view on using BCIs for locked in syndrome. Neuroethics 1: 119–132.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Clark, A., and D. Chalmers. 1998. The extended mind. Analysis 58: 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Clark, A. 2008. Supersizing the mind: embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Walter, S. 2010. Locked-in syndrome, BCI, and a confusion about embodied, embedded, extended, and enacted cognition. Neuroethics 3: 61–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Kübler, A., A. Furdea, S. Halder, and A. Hösle. 2008. Brain Painting—BCI meets art. In 4th international brain-computer interface workshop and training course. Graz University of Technology, ed. G.R. Müller-Putz, C. Brunner, R. Leeb, G. Pfurtscheller, and C. Neuper, 361–366. Austria: Verlag der Technischen Universität Graz.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Fodor, Jerry. 1987. Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind. MIT Press.

  19. Bauby, J.-D. 1997. The diving bell and the butterfly. London: Harper Perennial.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Clark, A. 2009. Spreading the joy: why the machinery of consciousness is (probably) still in the head. Mind 118: 963–993.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Kyselo, M., and S. Walter. 2009. Supersizing the mind. Philosophical Psychology 22: 803–807.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Adams, F., and K. Aizawa. 2010. Defending the bounds of cognition. In The extended mind, ed. R. Menary. Aldershot, Hants: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Adams, F., and K. Aizawa. 2009. The bounds of cognition. Blackwell: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Rupert, D.R. 2004. Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. Journal of Philosophy 101: 389–428.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Di Paolo, E. 2009. Extended life. Topoi 28: 9–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Thompson, E. 2007. Mind in life: biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Di Paolo, E.A., M. Rohde, and H. De Jaegher. 2007. Horizons for the enactive mind: values, social interaction and play. In Enaction: towards a new paradigm for cognitive science, ed. J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, and E.A. Di Paolo. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Weber, A., and F.J. Varela. 2002. Life after Kant: natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1: 97–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Varela, F.J. 1997. Patterns of life: intertwining identity and cognition. Brain and Cognition 34: 72–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Barandiaran, X., Rohde, M. and Di Paolo, E. 2009. Defining agency: individuality, normativity, asymmetry and spatio-temporality in action. Adaptive Behavior 17: 367–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Di Paolo, E. 2005. Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 4: 429–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Colombetti, G., and S. Torrance. 2009. Emotion and ethics: an inter-(en)active approach. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 8: 505–526.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Maturana, H. R. and Varela, F. J. 1980. Autopoiesis and Cognition: The Realization of the Living. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. 42. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

  34. De Jaegher, H. and Di Paolo, E. 2008. Making Sense in Participation: An Enactive Approach to Social Cognition. In Morganti, F., Carassa, A., Riva G. (Eds.) Enacting Intersubjectivity: A Cognitive and Social Perspective on the Study of Interactions Amsterdam, IOS Press.

  35. Varela, F.J., E. Thompson, and E. Rosch. 1991. The embodied mind: cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Torrance, S. 2005. In search of the enactive. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 4(4): 357–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Lulé, D. et al. 2009. Life can be worth living in locked-in syndrome, Progress in Brain Research, 177.

  38. Lutz, A., and E. Thompson. 2003. Neurophenomenology: integrating subjective experience and brain dynamics in the neuroscience of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies 10(9–10): 31–52.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Wolpaw, J. 2007. Brain–computer interfaces as new brain output pathways. The Journal of Physiology 579(3): 613–619.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer, Ezequiel Di Paolo, Markus I. Eronen, Rudolf Müllan, Frank Schumann and Sven Walter for valuable comments on earlier versions of the manuscript. My research is funded by a scholarship of the Research Training Group “Adaptivity in Hybrid Cognitive Systems”, University of Osnabrück, Germany.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Miriam Kyselo.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kyselo, M. Locked-in Syndrome and BCI - Towards an Enactive Approach to the Self. Neuroethics 6, 579–591 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-011-9104-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-011-9104-x

Keywords

Navigation