Skip to main content
Log in

Structural realism versus standard scientific realism: the case of phlogiston and dephlogisticated air

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The aim of this paper is to revisit the phlogiston theory to see what can be learned from it about the relationship between scientific realism, approximate truth and successful reference. It is argued that phlogiston theory did to some extent correctly describe the causal or nomological structure of the world, and that some of its central terms can be regarded as referring. However, it is concluded that the issue of whether or not theoretical terms successfully refer is not the key to formulating the appropriate form of scientific realism in response to arguments from theory change, and that the case of phlogiston theory is shown to be readily accommodated by ontic structural realism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Bergman, T. A. (1785). Dissertation on elective attractions (trans: Beddoes, T.). London. (First published in Latin as Dissertatio de attractionibus electives, 231–234 (1775).

  • Bird A. (2000) Thomas Kuhn. Acumen., Chesum

    Google Scholar 

  • Carrier M. (2004) Experimental success and the revelation of reality: The miracle argument for scientific realism. In: Carrier M. (eds) et al Knowledge and the world: Challenges beyond the science wars. Springer, Heidelberg, pp 137–161

    Google Scholar 

  • Carrier, M. (this volume).

  • Chang H. (2003) Preservative realism and its discontents: Revisiting caloric. Philosophy of Science 70: 902–912

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett D. (1991) Real patterns. Journal of Philosophy 88: 27–51

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elsamahi M. (2005) A critique of localised realism. Philosophy of Science 72: 1350–1360

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fahrbach, L. (this volume).

  • Field H. (1973) Theory change and the indeterminacy of reference. Journal of Philosophy 70: 462–481

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gale G. (1968) Phlogiston revisited: Explanatory models and conceptual change. Chemistry 41: 16–20

    Google Scholar 

  • Grandy R. (1973) Reference, meaning and belief. Journal of Philosophy 70: 439–452

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardin C. L., Rosenberg A. (1982) In defence of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science 49: 604–615

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoyningen-Huene P. (2008) Thomas Kuhn and the chemical revolution. Foundations of Chemistry 10: 101–115

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P. (1993) The advancement of science. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Koertege, N. (1969). The general correspondence principle: A study of relations between scientific theories. Doctoral Thesis, University of London.

  • Kuhn T. S. (1970) The structure of scientific revolutions. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman J. (1998) What is structural realism?. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 29: 409–424

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman J. (1998) What is structural realism?. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 29: 409–424

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman J. (2002) Understanding philosophy of science. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (2007). Structural realism. In E.N. Zalta (Eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://www.plato.stanford.edu/entries/structural-realism/.

  • Ladyman J., Ross D. (2007) Every thing must go: Metaphysics naturalized. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lange M. (2002) Baseball, pessimistic inductions and the turnover fallacy. Analysis 62: 281–285

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48, 19–49. (Reprinted in D. Papineau (Ed.), The philosophy of science (pp. 107–138). Oxford: Oxford University Press).

  • Laudan L. (1984) Realism without the real. Philosophy of Science 51: 156–162

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D. (1970) How to define theoretical terms. Journal of Philosophy 67: 17–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis P. (2001) Why the pessimistic induction is a fallacy. Synthese 129: 371–380

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyons T. D. (2006) Scientific realism and the Stratagema de Divide et Impera. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57: 537–560

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Magnus P. D., Callender C. (2004) Realist ennui and the base rate fallacy. Philosophy of Science 71: 320–338

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLeish C. (2005) Scientific realism bit by bit: Part I. Kitcher on reference. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 36: 667–685

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLeish C. (2006) Realism bit by bit: Part II. Disjunctive partial reference. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 37: 171–190

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave A. (1976) Why did oxygen supplant phlogiston? Research programmes in the chemical revolution. In: Howson C. (eds) Method and appraisal in the physical sciences. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 181–209

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Penrose R. (2004) The road to reality: A complete guide to the laws of the universe. Jonathan Cape, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Post H. (1971) Correspodence, invariance and heuristics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 2: 213–255

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos S. (1999) Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H. (1978) Meaning and the moral sciences. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Pyle A. (2000) The rationality of the chemical revolution. In: Nola R., Sankey H. (eds) After Popper, Kuhn and Feyerabend. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp 99–124

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (this volume).

  • Schurz G. (2009) When empirical success implies theoretical reference: A structural correspondence theorem. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60: 101–133

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanford P. K. (2003a) No refuge for realism: Selective confirmation and the history of science. Philosophy of Science 70: 913–925

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanford P. K. (2003b) Pyrrhic victories for scientific realism. Journal of Philosophy 11: 551–572

    Google Scholar 

  • Whewell W. (1837) The history of the inductive sciences (Vol. 3). John W Parker, London

    Google Scholar 

  • White J. H. (1932) The history of the phlogiston theory. Edward Arnold, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (1989). Structural realism: The best of both worlds? Dialectica, 43, 99–124. (Reprinted in D. Papineau (Ed.), The philosophy of science (pp. 139–165). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to James Ladyman.

Additional information

This paper is based on a talk with the same title given at the Theoretical Frameworks and Empirical Underdetermination workshop at the University of Düsseldorf on 10–12th April 2008. I am extremely grateful to Gerhard Schurz and Ioannis Votsis for organizing the event and inviting me, and to the participants for their comments. I am also heavily indebted to Andrew Pyle for generously sharing his extensive knowledge about the history and philosophy of phlogiston chemistry, and also to my student Bon Hyuk Koo for discussion of the place of phlogiston in the scientific realism debate.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Ladyman, J. Structural realism versus standard scientific realism: the case of phlogiston and dephlogisticated air. Synthese 180, 87–101 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-009-9607-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-009-9607-8

Keywords

Navigation