Skip to main content
Log in

Symposium on “Cognition and Rationality: Part I” The rationality of scientific discovery: abductive reasoning and epistemic mediators

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Mind & Society Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Philosophers have usually offered a number of ways of describing hypotheses generation, but all aim at demonstrating that the activity of generating hypotheses is paradoxical, illusory or obscure, and then not analysable. Those descriptions are often so far from Peircian pragmatic prescription and so abstract to result completely unknowable and obscure. The “computational turn” gives us a new way to understand creative processes in a strictly pragmatic sense. In fact, by exploiting artificial intelligence and cognitive science tools, computational philosophy allows us to test concepts and ideas previously conceived only in abstract terms. It is in the perspective of these actual computational models that I find the central role of abduction in the explanation of creative reasoning in science. Creativity and discovery are no more seen as a mysterious irrational process, but, thanks to constructive accounts, as a complex relationship among different inferential steps that can be clearly analysed and identified. I maintain that the computational philosophy analysis of model-based and manipulative abduction and of external and epistemic mediators is important not only to delineate the actual practice of abduction, but also to further enhance the development of programs computationally adequate in rediscovering, or discovering for the first time, for example, scientific hypotheses or mathematical theorems.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A perspective established by Reichenbach (1938) and Popper (1959).

  2. Magnani (2001a, 2002) introduces the concept of theoretical abduction. He maintains that there are two kinds of theoretical abduction, “sentential”, related to logic and to verbal/symbolic inferences, and “model-based”, related to the exploitation of internalized models of diagrams, pictures, etc., cf. below in this paper.

  3. Manipulative abduction and epistemic mediators are introduced and illustrated in Magnani 2001a.

  4. I derive this expression from the cognitive anthropologist Hutchins, that coins the expression “mediating structure” to refer to various external tools that can be built to cognitively help the activity of navigating in modern but also in “primitive” settings. Any written procedure is a simple example of a cognitive “mediating structure” with possible cognitive aims: “Language, cultural knowledge, mental models, arithmetic procedures, and rules of logic are all mediating structures too. So are traffic lights, supermarkets layouts, and the contexts we arrange for one another’s behaviour. Mediating structures can be embodied in artefacts, in ideas, in systems of social interactions” (Hutchins 1995, pp. 290–291).

  5. It is difficult to preserve precise spatial relationships using mental imagery, especially when one set of them has to be moved relative to another.

  6. It is Hutchins (1995, p. 114) that uses the expression “cognitive ecology” when explaining the role of internal and external cognitive navigation tools. More suggestions on manipulative abduction can be derived by the contributions collected in Morgan and Morrison (eds., 1999), dealing with the mediating role of scientific models between theory and the “real world”.

  7. The epistemic and cognitive role of mirror and unveiling diagrams in the discovery of non-Euclidean geometry is illustrated in Magnani 2002.

  8. This is mathematically justified in Magnani and Dossena 2005.

  9. Of course in the case we are using diagrams to demonstrate already known theorems (for instance in didactic settings), the strategy of manipulations is not necessary unknown and the result is not new.

  10. This approach in computer science, involving the use of diagram manipulations as forms of acceptable methods of reasoning, was opened by Gelernter’s Geometry Machine (1963), but the diagrams played a very secondary role.

References

  • Boden MA (1991) The creative mind: myths and mechanisms. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan BG (2001) Creativity at the metalevel. AAAI-2000 presidential address. AI Mag Fall 2001:13-28

    Google Scholar 

  • Cornuéjols A, Tiberghien A, Collet G (2000) A new mechanism for transfer between conceptual domains in scientific discovery and education. Found Sci 5(2):129-155 (special issue on Based reasoning in scientific discovery: Learning and discovery, ed by Magnani L, Nersessian NJ, Thagard P)

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelernter H (1963) Realization of a geometry theorem proving machine. In: Feigenbaum E, Feldman J (eds) Computers and thought. McGraw Hill, New York, pp 134-152

    Google Scholar 

  • Gooding D (1990) Experiment and the making of meaning. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins E (1995) Cognition in the wild. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant I (1929) Critique of pure reason (trans by Kemp Smith N). (Reprint 1998) MacMillan, London (originally published 1787)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn TS (1962) The structure of scientific revolutions. (2nd edn, 1997). University of Chicago, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindsay RK (1994) Understanding diagrammatic demonstrations. In: Ram A, Eiselt K (eds) Proceedings of the 16th annual conference of the cognitive science society. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Hillsdale, pp 572-576

  • Lindsay RK (1998) Using diagrams to understand geometry. Comput Intell 9(4):343-345

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindsay RK (2000) Playing with diagrams. In: Anderson M, Cheng P, Haarslev V (eds) Theory and application of diagrams: first international conference diagrams 2000. Springer, Berlin Heidelberg NewYork, pp 300-313

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani L (1992) Abductive reasoning: philosophical and educational perspectives in medicine. In: Evans DA, Patel VL (eds) Advanced models of cognition for medical training and practice. Springer, Berlin Heidelberg NewYork, pp 21-41

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani L (1999) Inconsistencies and creative abduction in science. In: AI and scientific creativity. Proceedings of the AISB99 symposium on scientific creativity. Society for the study of artificial intelligence and simulation of behaviour, Edinburgh College of Art and Division of Informatics, University of Edinburgh, Edinburgh, pp 1-18

  • Magnani L (2001a) Abduction, reason, and science. Processes of discovery and explanation. Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani L (2001b) Philosophy and geometry. Theoretical and historical issues. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani L (2002) Epistemic mediators and model-based discovery in science. In: Magnani L, Nersessian NJ (eds) Model-based reasoning: Science, technology, values. Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers, New York, pp 325-329

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani L, Dossena R (2005) Perceiving the infinite and then infinitesimal world: unveiling and optical diagrams in the construction of mathematical concepts. Found Sci 10:7-23

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan MS, Morrison M (1999) Models as mediators. Perspectives on natural and social science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Nersessian NJ (1999) Model-based reasoning in conceptual change. In: Magnani L, Nersessian NJ, Thagard P (eds) Model-based reasoning in scientific discovery. Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers, New York, pp 5-22

    Google Scholar 

  • Norman DA (1993) Things that make us smart defending human attributes in the age of the machines. Addison-Wesley, Reading

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce CS (1931-1958) Collected papers, 8 vols, ed by Hartshorne C and Weiss P (vols I-VI), and Burks AW (vols VII-VIII). Harvard University Press, Cambridge

  • Peirce CS (1986) Writings of Charles Sanders Peirce, A chronological edition, vol 3 (1872-1878). Indiana University Press, Bloomington

  • Piaget J (1974) Adaptation and intelligence. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper KR (1959) The logic of scientific discovery. Hutchison, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach H (1938) Experience and prediction. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson A (1966) Non standard analysis. North-Holland, Amsterdam

  • Sternberg RJ (1999) Handbook of creativity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sternberg RJ, Kaufman JC, Pretz JE (2002) The creativity conundrum: a propulsion model of kinds of creative contributions. Psychology Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard P (1992) Conceptual revolutions. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lorenzo Magnani.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Magnani, L. Symposium on “Cognition and Rationality: Part I” The rationality of scientific discovery: abductive reasoning and epistemic mediators. Mind & Society 5, 213–228 (2006). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11299-006-0018-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11299-006-0018-y

Keywords

Navigation