Skip to main content
Log in

The Easy Argument

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Suppose Ted is in an ordinary house in good viewing conditions and believes red, his table is red, entirely because he sees his table and its color; he also believes not-white, it is false that his table is white and illuminated by a red light, because not-white is entailed by red. The following three claims about this table case clash, but each seems plausible: 1. Ted’s epistemic position is strong enough for him to know red. 2. Ted cannot know not-white on the basis of red. 3. The epistemic closure principle, suitably restricted, is true. Stewart Cohen has called this three-way clash of intuitions the problem of easy knowledge. If we wish to resolve the clash without accepting skepticism, we seem to have two options. According to the hard argument, the best response is to reject 3. The easy argument rejects 2. But there may be a third alternative, the reverse argument, which rejects 1 without ceding a substantial amount of ground to the skeptic. In this essay I criticize recent versions of the reverse argument and the hard argument, thereby lending support to the easy argument.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Armstrong, D. (1973). Belief, Truth and Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (2002). Basic knowledge and the problem of easy knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65(2), 309–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, S. (2005). Why basic knowledge is easy knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 75(2), 417–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1970). Epistemic operators. Journal of Philosophy, 67, 1007–1023.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (2003). Skepticism: what perception teaches in Luper 2003b.

  • Dretske, F. (2005). Is knowledge closed under known entailment? in Steup 2005.

  • Fumerton, R. (1995). Metaepistemology and skepticism. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1968). Knowledge, inference and explanation. American Philosophical Quarterly, 5, 164–173.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1986). Change in view, Cambridge: MIT Press; partially reprinted in S. Luper, Essential Knowledge, New York: Pearson Longman, 2004.

  • Harman, G., & Sherman, B. (2004). Knowledge, assumptions, lotteries. Philosophical Issues, 14, 492–500.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (2006) Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kyburg, H. (1961). Conjunctivitis. Probability and the logic of rational belief. Middletown, Conn.: Wesleyan University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luper, S. (1984). The epistemic predicament: knowledge, nozickian tracking, and skepticism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 62, 26–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luper, S. (ed.) (1987a). The possibility of knowledge: nozick and his critics, Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luper, S. (1987b). The causal indicator analysis of knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 47, 563–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luper, S. (2003a). Indiscernability skepticism. In S. Luper 2003b.

  • Luper, S. (2003b) The Skeptics. In S. Luper (ed.), Hampshire: Ashgate Publishing, Limited.

  • Luper, S. (2005). Epistemic closure principle. Stanford University encyclopedia of philosophy. In: Edward N. Zalta (Ed.), 2002.

  • Luper, S. (2006). Dretske on knowledge closure. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 84, 379–394, (2006).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luper, S. (2007). Re-reading G. E. Moore’s ‘certainty. Philosophical Papers, 36(1), 151–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2000). Neither contextualism nor skepticism. In Luper 2003b, 165–182.

  • Steup, M., & Sosa, E. (eds.) (2005). Contemporary Debates in Epistemology. Blackwell, Malden, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Cleve, J. (2003). Is knowledge easy-or impossible? Externalism as the Only Alternative to Skepticism. In Luper 2003b, 45–61.

  • Vogel, J. (1990). Are there counterexamples to the closure principle? In M. Roth & G. Ross (eds.) Doubting: Contemporary perspectives on skepticism. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vogel, J. (2000). Reliabilism leveled. Journal of Philosophy, 97, 602–623.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

A brief version of this essay was presented at Bled Conference on Epistemology, May 28-June 2, 2007. I thank the participants, my colleague Curtis Brown, and anonymous referees for their comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Steven Luper.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Luper, S. The Easy Argument. Acta Anal 22, 321–331 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-007-0014-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-007-0014-9

Keywords

Navigation