Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Précis of Doing without Concepts

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Notes

  1. Names of concepts are written in small caps.

  2. I also use these criteria to argue against hybrid theories of concepts, which hold that concepts have parts that store different kinds of information and that tend to be used in distinct processes.

References

  • Ashby, F. G., & Maddox, W. T. (2004). Human category learning. Annual Review of Psychology, 56, 149–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L. W. (1999). Perceptual symbol systems. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22, 577–660.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 78, 67–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dove, G. (2009). Beyond perceptual symbols: A call for representational pluralism. Cognition, 110, 412–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, K. (2009). What concepts do. Synthese, 170, 289–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1998). Concepts, where cognitive science went wrong. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (2003). Is it a bird? Problems with old and new approaches to the theory of concepts. TLS, 17 January 2003, 3–4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (2008). LOT 2: The language of thought revisited. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., & Lakoff, G. (2005). The brain’s concepts: The role of the sensory-motor system in conceptual knowledge. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 21, 455–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A. (2003). The theory as an alternative to the innateness hypothesis. In L. Antony & N. Hornstein (Eds.), Chomsky and his critics. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., Glymour, C., Sobel, D., Schulz, L., Kushnir, T., & Danks, D. (2004). A theory of causal learning in children: Causal maps and Bayes nets. Psychological Review, 111, 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hampton, J. A. (1979). Polymorphous concepts in semantic memory. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 18, 441–461.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hampton, J. A. (2006). Concepts as prototypes. In B. H. Ross (Ed.), The psychology of learning and motivation: Advances in research and theory (Vol. 46, pp. 79–113). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laurence, S., & Margolis, E. (1999). Concepts and cognitive science. In E. Margolis & S. Laurence (Eds.), Concepts, core readings (pp. 3–82). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2005). Concepts are not a natural kind. Philosophy of Science, 72, 444–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2006a). Two dogmas of neo-empiricism. Philosophy Compass, 1, 398–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2006b). How to split concepts. Reply to Piccinini and Scott. Philosophy of Science, 73, 410–418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2007). Concept empiricism: A methodological critique. Cognition, 104, 19–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2009). Doing without concepts. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mahon, B. Z., & Caramazza, A. (2008). A critical look at the embodied cognition hypothesis and a new proposal for grounding conceptual content. Journal of Physiology–Paris, 102, 59–70.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahon, B. Z., & Caramazza, A. (2009). Concepts and categories: A cognitive neuropsychological perspective. Annual Review of Psychology, 60, 27–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mallon, R., Machery, E., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. P. (2009). Against arguments from reference. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 79, 332–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, E. (1994). A reassessment of the shift from the classical theory of concepts to prototype theory. Cognition, 51, 73–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, E. (1995). The significance of the theory analogy in the psychological study of concepts. Mind and Language, 10, 45–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, E., & Laurence, S. (2006). Concepts. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available at http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/concepts/.

  • Martin, A. (2007). The representation of object concepts in the brain. Annual Review of Psychology, 58, 25–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Medin, D. L., & Schaffer, M. M. (1978). Context theory of classification learning. Psychological Review, 85, 207–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, G. L. (2002). The big book of concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, G. L., & Medin, D. L. (1985). The role of theories in conceptual coherence. Psychological Review, 92, 289–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nosofsky, R. M. (1992). Exemplar-based approach to relating categorization, identification, and recognition. In F. G. Ashby (Ed.), Multidimensional models of perception and cognition (pp. 363–393). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1992). A study of concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (2008). Truly understood. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G., & Scott, S. (2006). Splitting concepts. Philosophy of Science, 73, 390–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. J. (2002). Furnishing the mind: Concepts and their perceptual basis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of “meaning”. In H. Putnam (Ed.), Philosophical papers, Vol. 2: Mind, language, and reality (pp. 215–271). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1969). Natural kinds. In W. V. O. Quine (Ed.), Ontological relativity and other essays (pp. 114–138). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rey, G. (1983). Concepts and stereotypes. Cognition, 15, 237–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rey, G. (2009). Review of E. Machery, Doing without Concepts. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews.

  • Rips, L. J. (1989). Similarity, typicality, and categorization. In S. Vosniadou & A. Ortony (Eds.), Similarity and analogical reasoning (pp. 21–59). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rosch, E., & Mervis, C. B. (1975). Family resemblance: Studies in the internal structure of categories. Cognitive Psychology, 7, 573–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1948). Human knowledge: Its scope and its limits. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. P. (1983). From folk psychology to cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. P. (1996). Deconstructing the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tenenbaum, J. B., Griffiths, T. L., & Niyogi, S. (2007). Intuitive theories as grammars for causal inference. In A. Gopnik & L. Schulz (Eds.), Causal learning: Psychology, philosophy, and computation (pp. 301–322). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Edouard Machery.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Machery, E. Précis of Doing without Concepts . Philos Stud 149, 401–410 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-010-9527-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-010-9527-y

Keywords

Navigation