Skip to main content
Log in

The Bleak Implications of Moral Psychology

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Neuroethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this article, I focus on two claims made by Appiah in Experiments in Ethics: Doris’s and Harman’s criticism of virtue ethics fails, and moral psychology can be used to identify erroneous moral intuitions. I argue that both claims are erroneous.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In this article, I follow Appiah in distinguishing moral psychology from moral philosophy, but I should note that in my mind, moral psychology is both empirical and philosophical (for a similar view, see the introduction of the forthcoming Handbook of Moral Psychology).

  2. I highly recommend reading the endnotes where much of the research on which Appiah relies is described and referenced.

  3. Appiah distinguishes moral and ethical questions as follows (37): Moral questions concern what we should do; ethical questions concern what life we should live.

  4. It might be helpful to think about this assumption in terms of an analysis of variance. The idea, then, is that people’s character accounts for most of the variance in their behavior.

  5. Doris [5] discusses this reply, noting that it raises a specific empirical question: To which extent are people able to comply with these norms?

  6. It does not matter whether Harman [3] and Doris [4, 5] originally conceived of the situationist threat in these terms. Doris’s [8] arguments are close to the argument presented here.

  7. It might be helpful to think about this in terms of factor analysis. Suppose people really have characters. Then, if one were to analyze someone’s behavior factorially, a single factor would emerge (in contrast to several factors corresponding to the diverse psychological causes).

  8. To clarify, the issue does not concern the unity of the virtues (viz. whether courage, generosity, temperance, etc., necessarily go together). Rather, it concerns the kind of unity among beliefs, desires, values, emotions, etc., that is required for someone to have a given character trait. For instance, to be courageous is to be disposed to have specific beliefs, desires, values, etc., with respect to situations of danger.

  9. Of course, agency can be more or less unified.

  10. Interestingly, in the last chapter of Experiments in Ethics, Appiah argues that the importance of intuitions in moral philosophy is regrettable. For simplicity, I will overlook this claim in what follows.

  11. As Appiah remarks, moral theories have to walk a tight rope between being too conservative (agreeing with many commonsense moral intuitions) and being too reformative (disagreeing with many moral intuitions).

  12. Greene seems to hold that automaticity goes with irrationality, while others propose that it goes with rationality (e.g., [32]).

  13. Examining the implications of this situation is beyond the scope of this article.

References

  1. Levy, N. 2006. Cognitive scientific challenges to morality. Philosophical Psychology 9: 567–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. Sinnott-Armstrong, W. 2008. Framing moral intuitions. In Moral psychology, volume 2: The cognitive science of morality, ed. W. Sinnott-Armstrong, 47–76. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Harman, G. 1999. Moral philosophy meets social psychology: virtue ethics and the fundamental attribution error. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99: 315–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Doris, J.M. 1998. Persons, situations, and virtue ethics. Noûs 32: 504–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Doris, J.M. 2002. Lack of character. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Isen, A.M., and P.F. Levin. 1972. The effect of feeling good on helping: cookies and kindness. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 21: 384–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Appiah, K.A. 2008. Experiments in ethics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Doris, J.M. Forthcoming. A natural history of the self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  9. Hursthouse, R. 1999. On virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  10. McAdams, D.P., and J.L. Pals. 2006. A new big five. Fundamental principles for an integrative science of personality. American Psychologist 61: 204–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Epstein, S. 1979. The stability of behavior: I. On predicting most of the people much of the time. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 37: 1097–1126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Sabini, J., and M. Silver. 2005. Lack of character? Situationism critiqued. Ethics 115: 535–562.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Dewey, J. 1897. My pedagogic creed. School Journal 54: 77–80.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Prestwitch, D.L. 2004. Character education in America’s school. School Community Journal 14: 139–150.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Greene, J.D., and J. Haidt. 2002. How (and where) does moral judgment work? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 6: 517–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Wilson, T.D. 2002. Strangers to ourselves. Discovering the adaptive unconscious. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Bargh, J.A., and E.L. Williams. 2006. The automaticity of social life. Current Directions in Psychological Science 15: 1–4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Monteith, M.J., J.W. Sherman, and P.G. Devine. 1998. Suppression as a stereotype control strategy. Personality and Social Psychology Review 2: 63–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Richeson, J.A., and J.N. Shelton. 2007. Negotiating interracial interactions: cost, consequences, and possibilities. Current Directions in Psychological Science 16: 316–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Nosek, B.A., A.G. Greenwald, and M.R. Banaji. 2007. The implicit association test at age 7: A methodological and conceptual review. In Automatic processes in social thinking and behavior, ed. J.A. Bargh, 265–292. Philadelphia: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Kelly, D., and E. Roedder. 2008. Racial cognition and the ethics of implicit bias. Philosophy Compass 3: 522–540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Kelly, D., E. Machery, and R. Mallon. 2010. Racial cognition and normative theory. In Handbook of moral philosophy, ed. J.M. Doris et al. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Faucher, L., & Machery, E. (2009). Racism: against Jorge Garcia’s moral and psychological monism. Philosophy of Social Sciences 39: 41–62.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Payne, B.K. 2006. Weapon bias: split-second decisions and unintended stereotyping. Current Directions in Psychological Science 15(6): 287–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Payne, B.K. 2005. Conceptualizing control in social cognition: how executive functioning modulates the expression of automatic stereotyping. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 89: 488–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Gregg, A.P., B. Seibt, and M.R. Banaji. 2006. Easier done than undone: asymmetry in the malleability of implicit preferences. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 90: 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Doris, J.M., and S. Stich. 2005. As a matter of fact: Empirical perspectives on ethics. In The Oxford handbook of contemporary analytic philosophy, ed. F. Jackson and M. Smith. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Tversky, A., and D. Kahneman. 1981. The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science 211: 453–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Greene, J.D., S.A. Morelli, K. Lowenberg, L.E. Nystrom, and J.D. Cohen. 2008. Cognitive load selectively interferes with utilitarian moral judgment. Cognition 107(3): 44–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Greene, J.D., L.E. Nystrom, A.D. Engell, J.M. Darley, and J.D. Cohen. 2004. The neural bases of cognitive conflict and control in moral judgment. Neuron 44: 389–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Greene, J.D., R.B. Sommerville, L.E. Nystrom, J.M. Darley, and J.D. Cohen. 2001. An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science 293: 2105–2108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Woodward, J., and J. Allman. 2008. Moral intuition: its neural substrates and normative significance. Journal of Physiology-Paris 101: 179–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. De Brigard, F. (2010). If you like it, does it matter if it’s real? Philosophical Psychology 23: 43–57.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Gyenis, B., & Machery, E. (2008). Unpublished data.

  35. Stuart, A., & Hatleback, E. (ms). Identification, intuition, and moral dilemmas.

  36. Greene, J. D., Cohen, J. D., Nystrom, L. E., Lindsell, D., Clarke, A. C., & Lowenberg, K. (2009). Pushing moral buttons: The interaction between personal force and intention in moral judgment. Cognition 111: 364–371.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank John Doris, Gil Harman, Neil Levy, and Walter Sinnott-Armstrong for their comments on a previous version of this article. I would also like to thank the readers of the blog Experimental Philosophy (www.experimentalphilosophy.typepad.com) for their comments on this article—particularly, Anne Jacobson, Lisa Lederer, Tamler Sommers, Jussi Suikkanen. A version of this article was also presented in Princeton.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Edouard Machery.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Machery, E. The Bleak Implications of Moral Psychology. Neuroethics 3, 223–231 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-010-9063-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-010-9063-7

Keywords

Navigation