Skip to main content
Log in

Founding Quantum Theory on the Basis of Consciousness

  • Published:
Foundations of Physics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

In the present work, quantum theory is founded on the framework of consciousness, in contrast to earlier suggestions that consciousness might be understood starting from quantum theory. The notion of streams of consciousness, usually restricted to conscious beings, is extended to the notion of a Universal/Global stream of conscious flow of ordered events. The streams of conscious events which we experience constitute sub-streams of the Universal stream. Our postulated ontological character of consciousness also consists of an operator which acts on a state of potential consciousness to create or modify the likelihoods for later events to occur and become part of the Universal conscious flow. A generalized process of measurement-perception is introduced, where the operation of consciousness brings into existence, from a state of potentiality, the event in consciousness. This is mathematically represented by (a) an operator acting on the state of potential consciousness before an actual event arises in consciousness and (b) the reflecting of the result of this operation back onto the state of potential consciousness for comparison in order for the event to arise in consciousness. Beginning from our postulated ontology that consciousness is primary and from the most elementary conscious contents, such as perception of periodic change and motion, quantum theory follows naturally as the description of the conscious experience.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. Wheeler J.A., Zurek W.H. (1983). Quantum Theory and Measurement. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  2. Einstein A., Podolsky B., Rosen N. (1935). Phys. Rev 47:777

    Article  MATH  ADS  Google Scholar 

  3. E. Schrödinger, Proc. Cambridge Phil. Soc. 31, 555 (1935); ibid 32, 446 (1936).

  4. Selleri F., van der Merwe A. (1990). Quantum Paradoxes and Physical Reality. Kluwer Academic, Dordrecht See also references therein.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  5. N. Bohr, Atomic Theory and the Description of Nature (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1934); Atomic Theory and Human Knowledge (Wiley, New York, 1958).

  6. W. Heisenberg, The Physical Principles of the Quantum Theory (Dover, New York, 1930); Physics and Philosophy, (Harper and Row, NY, 1958).

  7. D. Bohm, Phys. Rev. 85, 166 (1952); ibid, 85, 180 (1952).

  8. Everett H. III. (1957). Rev. Mod. Phys 29:463

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  Google Scholar 

  9. Ballentine L.E. (1970). Rev. Mod. Phys 42:358

    Article  MATH  ADS  Google Scholar 

  10. Bell J.S., Aspect A. (1987). Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics: Collected Papers on Quantum Philosophy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  11. van der Merwe A., Selleri F., Tarozzi G. Microphysical Reality and Quantum Formalism, Eds., Vols I and II (Kluwer Academic, Dordrecht, 1988).

  12. H. P. Stapp, Mind, Matter and Quantum Mechanics (Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 2003); H. P. Stapp, Found. Phys. 10, 767 (1980).

  13. Schwartz J.M., Stapp H.P., Beauregard M. Phil. Trans. R Soc. B 360(1458), 1306 (2005).

    Google Scholar 

  14. E. Schrödinger, What is Life? And Mind and Matter (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1967). Studying the entire book is strongly recommended and in particular Chap. 3, p. 126 and Chap. 4, p. 139.

  15. Schrödinger E. (1954). Nature and the Greeks. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  16. E. P. Wigner, “Quantum Theory and Measurement,” in J. A. Wheeler, and W. H. Zurek, eds. (Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1983), pp. 260 and 325.

  17. J. Von Neumann, Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Chap. VI (Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1955), p. 417.

  18. F. London and E. Bauer, “Quantum Theory and Measurement,” in J. A. Wheeler, and W. H. Zurek, eds. (Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1983), p. 217.

  19. W. Pauli and C. G. Jung, Atom and the Archetype, Pauli/Jung, Letters, 1932–1958. C. A. Meier, ed. (Princeton University Press, Princeton, 2001).

  20. R. Penrose, The Emperor’s New Mind (Oxford University Press, New York, 1989); The Shadows of the Mind (Oxford University Press, New York, 1994).

  21. Mavromatos N.E., Nanopoulos D.V. (1998). Int. J. Mod. Phys B 12:517

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  22. Pöppel E. Trends Cognit Sci. 1:56–61 (1997).

    Google Scholar 

  23. Aristotle, Posterior Analytics II 19, 99b28-29:

  24. I. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason (1781), see translation in English by P. Max Müller (Anchor books, New York, 1966).

  25. B. Spinoza, Ethics; edited and translated by G. H. R. Parkinson (Oxford University Press, New York, 2000).

  26. Whitehead A.N. (1933). Adventures of Ideas. Macmillan, New York, p. 228

    Google Scholar 

  27. C. G. Jung, Psychological Types, p. 567 (Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1971); C. G. Jung, The Integration of the Personality (Farrar and Rinehart, New York, 1939); C. G. Jung, Psychology of the Unconscious (Dodd, New York, 1916).

  28. The idea of something “potentially existing” was discussed by Aristotle, see, e.g., Physics, 186a1-3. This can be translated as follows: “..., because the one exists in potentia and in actuality.”

  29. Parmenides, On Nature, Pre-Socratic Greek Philosopher, born in 510 B.C. See The Fragments of Parmenides, A. H. Coxon (Assen, Netherlands, 1986). See also Ref. [30].

  30. Parmenides, Presented by Plato, p. 920, Ref. [31].

  31. Plato, “Collected Dialogs”, eds. E. Hamilton and H. Cairns, (Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1980).

  32. S. Vivekananda, The Complete Works of Swami Vivekananda, Mayavati memorial edn. (Advaita Ashrama, Calcutta, 1965).

  33. Krishnamurti J., Bohm D. (1985). The Ending of Time. Gollancz, London

    Google Scholar 

  34. We postulate that the seat of consciousness cannot be matter-energy itself because matter is itself an experience of consciousness; namely the experience of matter is given us posteriori but that which perceives matter, that which has the experience, must be ready for the experience to occur a priori.(24)

  35. E. Webb, Philosophers of Consciousness, Chapter 2, “B. Lonergan, Consciousness as experience and operation” (University of Washington Press, Seattle, 1988), p. 53.

  36. The original meaning of the Greek word “phenomenon” is “appearance”, namely, that which appears in consciousness.

  37. When a sentient being is examined to study “his” consciousness using all presently available instrumentation, the being is turned into an object (See Ref. [14], Chapter 3, “The principle of objectivation”). Subject is the experience of oneself. For example, if we follow the nerve excitation caused by the molecules of a flower which interact with those of his nose we will never “see” or experience the aroma. All we will be able to see is the electromagnetic imprint, the pointer which ultimately the subject experiences. Some people are inclined to think that this is not the final stage, that somehow another part of the brain has looked at this imprint and interpreted it. However, we have already included this, namely, the imprint we are considering is the one produced in the brain after this process, namely, it is the collective neural excitations including the neurons that process all the series of signals and their translations to other signals. See also, Ref. [14], Chapter 6, “The mystery of the sensual qualities”.

  38. D. H. Hubel and T. N. Wiesel, J. Physiol. 148, 574–591 (1959).

  39. Hubel D.H. (1995). Eye, Brain, and Vision. Scientific American Library Series, New York

    Google Scholar 

  40. Eccles J.C. (1994). How the Self Controls its Brain. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  41. Rieke F., Baylor D.A. (1998). Rev. Mod. Phys 70:1027

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  42. Yau K.-W., Baylor D.A. (1989). Ann. Rev. Neurosci 12:289

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  43. A. K. Engel, P. Konig, A. K. Kreiter, T. B. Schillen, and W. Singer, Trends Neurosci. 15, 218 (1992); C. M. Gray, J. Comput. Neurosci. 1, 11 (1994); P. Fries, J.-H Schöder, P. R. Roelfsema, W. Singer, and A. K. Engerl, J. Neurosci. 22, 3739 (2002).

  44. Baker C.L. Jr., Cynader M.S. (1986). J. Neurophysiol 55(6):1136

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  45. A. Aspect, P. Grangier, and G. Roger, Phys. Rev. Lett. 49, 91 (1982); ibid, 47, 460 (1981); A. Aspect, J. Dalibard, and G. Roger, Phys. Rev. Lett. 49, 1804 (1982).

  46. D. Bouwmeester et al., Nature 390, 575 (1997). D. Boschi et al., Phys. Rev. Lett. 80(6), 1121–1125 (1998); I. Marcikic et al., Nature 421, 509 (2003); M. Riebe et al., Nature 429, 734 (2004); M. D. Barrett et al., Nature 429, 737 (2004).

  47. Bohm D. (1979). Quantum Mechanics. Dover, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Efstratios Manousakis.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Manousakis, E. Founding Quantum Theory on the Basis of Consciousness. Found Phys 36, 795–838 (2006). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-006-9049-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-006-9049-9

Keywords

Navigation