Skip to main content
Log in

In defense of nativism

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper takes a fresh look at the nativism–empiricism debate, presenting and defending a nativist perspective on the mind. Empiricism is often taken to be the default view both in philosophy and in cognitive science. This paper argues, on the contrary, that there should be no presumption in favor of empiricism (or nativism), but that the existing evidence suggests that nativism is the most promising framework for the scientific study of the mind. Our case on behalf of nativism has four parts. (1) We characterize nativism’s core commitments relative to the contemporary debate between empiricists and nativists, (2) we present the positive case for nativism in terms of two central nativist arguments (the poverty of the stimulus argument and the argument from animals), (3) we respond to a number of influential objections to nativist theories, and (4) we explain the nativist approach to the conceptual system.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For recent critiques of nativist theorizing, see Buller (2005), Cowie (1999), Elman et al. (1996), Griffiths et al. (2009), Prinz (2002), Scholz and Pullum (2006).

  2. For a range of nativist theories, see Carruthers et al. (2005, 2006, 2007).

  3. See Cowie (1999) for an overview and analysis of the different objectives of historical and contemporary theorists. Among contemporary theorists, the psychological orientation also includes a debate about the relation between perception and cognition, where some self-described empiricists maintain that all mental representations are perceptual-motor representations. On this view, there is no such thing as fully abstract thought. See esp. Prinz (2002). Though Prinz’s empiricism is officially neutral about the status of innate concepts (pp. 195–196), it is clear that concerns about innateness are a motivating factor for proponents of his brand of empiricism.

  4. Though our focus is on the contemporary dispute between empiricists and nativists, it’s worth noting that the disagreement about the structures and processes underlying development is also prominent in the historical philosophical dispute. For example, Hume epitomizes the empiricist strategy in invoking just a few domain-general principles of association, and Descartes the nativist strategy in invoking distinct systems for geometrical knowledge and language. For a valuable discussion of the psychological strand in historical nativist thinking and its relation to contemporary nativism, see Chomsky (2009).

  5. For these reasons, it would be more accurate to refer to Empiricist Acquisition Bases (which are empiricist to varying degrees) and likewise Nativist Acquisition Bases (which are nativist to varying degrees).

  6. Another way of stating this is to use the term Acquisition Base to refer neutrally to the set of psychological mechanisms, states, and processes that ultimately explain the acquisition of all traits that are acquired via psychological processes. (In saying that these mechanisms, states, and processes ultimately explain the acquisition of all psychological traits, we are highlighting the fact that these items and their components are not themselves acquired via psychological processes.) Given this general notion of an Acquisition Base, the dispute between nativists and empiricists turns on the character of the Acquisition Base.

  7. This mistaken assumption is often expressed in terms of the slogan that learned and innate are opposites. But while it is certainly very plausible that if a psychological trait is learned it can’t be innate, it does not follow that learned traits are off limits for nativists. The reorientation that we are proposing (toward the character of the psychological systems involved in acquisition) opens the way for nativists to explain learning by appealing to distinctively nativist systems of acquisition, i.e., ones that appear in the Nativist Acquisition Base.

  8. Carey uses this example to illustrate that it isn’t problematic to attribute domain-specific acquisition systems to animals. We wholeheartedly agree. See the argument from animals below.

  9. For related arguments, see Gallistel et al. (1991) and Carruthers (2006).

  10. For overviews of related empirical work, see Gallistel (1990) and Shettleworth (2009).

  11. Piaget’s views were based on observations of children failing tasks that involve searching and reaching, as when 6-month-olds cease trying to obtain an object once it is covered by a blanket (Piaget 1954). More recent work in developmental psychology questions the emphasis on manual search and relies instead on measures of infants’ attention. One technique is to use looking time to infer which of two events is the more expected. For a useful overview of how this method supports conclusions about the way that infants represent the physical world, see Baillargeon (2004).

  12. For an overview of the field of evolutionary psychology, see Pinker (1997), Buss (2005).

  13. Chomsky has always resisted the idea that evolutionary theory has anything useful to contribute to our understanding of the structure of the language faculty; see, e.g., Chomksy (1980). And Fodor is one of evolutionary psychology’s staunchest critics; see, e.g., Fodor (2000), the title of which is meant to indicate his negative reaction to Pinker (1997).

  14. In these experiments, the monophagous feeders (vampire bats) weren’t directly compared to rats. They were compared to other species of bats, ones with varied diets. As a result, the adaptationist explanation made two substantive and correct predictions—that the vampire bats wouldn’t develop the taste aversion and that the other species of bat would.

  15. Historically, a further reason why philosophers have had trouble recognizing the complexity of the mind is that they relied too heavily on introspection. While this is not the case for contemporary philosophers whose work is informed by the cognitive sciences, philosophers who are somewhat at a distance from the scientific study of the mind may not realize that there is no longer any serious scientific dispute about the enormous extent to which unconscious mental processes dominate mental life and consequently about the fact that introspection is often a poor guide to the mind’s working. See, e.g., Searle (1992). It is no coincidence that Searle is skeptical both about the unconscious and about standard nativist models of language acquisition.

  16. For some noteworthy recent proposals, see Ariew (1996), Cowie (1999), Sober (1999), Wimsatt (1999), Samuels (2002), Mallon and Weinberg (2006), Khalidi, (2007), Mameli (2008).

  17. It also isn’t about the ordinary use of the term innate. As theoretical frameworks regarding the study of the mind, nativism and empiricism are no more beholden to the everyday use of a term than any other scientific endeavor.

  18. While empiricists may endorse some domain-specific acquisition systems, the dispute about the Acquisition Base remains. This is because they will generally suppose that such domain-specific systems are themselves acquired on the basis of more fundamental domain-general ones. See, e.g., Karmiloff-Smith’s treatment of acquired mental modules (Karmiloff-Smith 1992).

  19. Notice as well that to the extent that nativism relies on the notion of innateness, so does empiricism. So it would be a major double standard to hold it against nativism that the notion of innateness is ill-defined, while simultaneously seeing this as an advantage of empiricism, as many empiricists seem to do.

  20. Alternatively, Fodor’s view could be expressed in terms of the claim that such concepts are part of the Acquisition Base.

  21. We’ve argued against Fodor’s radical concept nativism elsewhere; see Laurence and Margolis (2002). We should note that Fodor’s views on innate concepts have changed somewhat (see Fodor 2008). Nonetheless, Fodor continues to be skeptical of learning models, and his current biological approach to concept acquisition inherits many of the problems associated with his earlier view; see Margolis and Laurence (2011) for a critical assessment.

  22. Although nativism shouldn’t be identified with the view that there are innate psychological traits, this doesn’t mean that nativists should be shy about postulating that some concepts are part of the Acquisition Base. The examples cited in the text are all ones where there is either ample empirical evidence, or persuasive theoretical considerations, in support of this claim.

  23. For cross-cultural evidence, see Atran and Medin (2008); for an overview of the disparate research on essentialist thinking in children, see Gelman (2003).

  24. Notice that what makes this a nativist model isn’t the supposition of a “religion module” or the claim that certain religious concepts are part of the Nativist Acquisition Base. The crucial point is simply that the acquisition of the concepts is substantially dependent on a Nativist Acquisition Base through the orchestration of a number of domain-specific cognitive systems in such an Acquisition Base.

References

  • Ariew, A. (1996). Innateness and canalization. Philosophy of Science, 63, S19–S27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Atran, S., & Medin, D. (2008). The native mind and the cultural construction of nature. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baillargeon, R. (2004). Infants’ physical world. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 13, 89–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyer, P. (2001). Religion explained: The evolutionary origins of religious thought. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. A. (1999). Cambrian intelligence: The early history of the new AI. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buller, D. J. (2005). Adapting minds: Evolutionary psychology and the persistent quest for human nature. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buss, D. (Ed.). (2005). The handbook of evolutionary psychology. Hoboken: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carey, S. (2010). The origin of concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2006). The architecture of the mind: Massive modularity and the flexibility of thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P., Laurence, S., & Stich, S. (Eds.). (2005). The innate mind: Structure and content. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P., Laurence, S., & Stich, S. (Eds.). (2006). The innate mind: Culture and cognition. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P., Laurence, S., & Stich, S. (Eds.). (2007). The innate mind: Foundations and the future. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomksy, N. (1980). Rules and representations. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1959). Review of verbal behavior. Language, 35:26–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1968/2006). Language and mind (3rd ed.). New York: Cambridge University Press.

  • Chomsky, N. (2009). Cartesian linguistics: A chapter in the history of rationalist thought (3rd ed.). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cowie, F. (1999). What’s within? Nativism reconsidered. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crain, S., & Pietroski, P. (2001). Nature, nurture, and universal grammar. Linguistic and Philosophy, 24, 139–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crain, S., & Thorton, R. (1998). Investigations in universal grammar: A guide to experiments on the acquisition of syntax and semantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eibl-Eibesfeldt, I. (1989). Human ethology. New York: Aldine de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elman, J. L., Bates, E. A., Johnson, M. H., Karmiliff-Smith, A., Parisi, D., & Plunkett, K. (1996). Rethinking innateness: A connectionist perspective on development. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1975). The language of thought. New York: Tomas Y. Crowell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1981). The present status of the innateness controversy. In J. A. Fodor (Ed.), Representations: Philosophical essays on the foundations of cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (2000). The mind doesn’t work that way. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (2008). LOT2: The language of thought revisited. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franks, N., Mallon, E. B., Bray, H. E., Hamilton, M. J., & Mischler, T. C. (2003). Strategies for choosing between alternatives with different attributes: exemplified by house-hunting ants. Animal Behaviour, 65, 215–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel, C. R. (1990). The organization of learning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel, C. R., Brown, A. L., Carey, S., Gelman, R., & Keil, F. C. (1991). Lessons from animal learning for the study of cognitive development. In S. Carey & R. Gelman (Eds.), The epigenesis of mind: Essays in biology and cognition. Hillsdale, NJ: LEA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel, C. R., & Gibbon, J. (2002). The symbolic foundations of conditioned behavior. Hillsdale, NJ: LEA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garcia, J., & Koelling, R. (1966). The relation of cue to consequence in avoidance learning. Psychonomic Science, 4, 123–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelman, G. (2003). The essential child: Origins of essentialism in everyday thought. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1967). The epistemological argument. Synthese, 17, 23–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1969). Emperor’s new ideas. In S. Hook (Ed.), Language and philosophy. New York: NYU Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, J., & Gould, C. (1995). The honey bee. New York: W.H. Freeman & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P., Machery, E., & Linquist, S. (2009). The vernacular concept of innateness. Mind & Language, 24, 605–630.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M. H., Bolhuis, J. J., & Horn, G. (1985). Interaction between acquired preferences and developing predispositions during imprinting. Animal Behaviour, 13, 1000–1006.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karmiloff-Smith, A. (1992). Beyond modularity: A developmental perspective on cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khalidi, N. (2007). Innate cognitive capacities. Mind and Language, 22, 92–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laurence, S., & Margolis, E. (2001). The poverty of the stimulus argument. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 52, 217–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laurence, S., & Margolis, E. (2002). Radical concept nativism. Cognition, 86(1), 22–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laurence, S., & Margolis, E. (forthcoming). The limits of thought. In E. Margolis & S. Laurence (eds.), Concepts: New essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Loomis, J. M., Klatzky, R. L., Golledge, R. G., & Philbeck, J. W. (1999). Human navigation by path integration. In R. Golledge (Ed.), Wayfinding behavior: Cognitive mapping and other spatial process. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mallon, R., & Weinberg, J. (2006). Innateness as closed process invariance. Philosophy of Science, 73, 323–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mameli, M. (2008). On innateness: The clutter hypothesis and the cluster hypothesis. Journal of Philosophy, 105, 719–736.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, E. (1998). How to acquire a concept. Mind & Language, 13, 347–369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, E., & Laurence, S. (2011). Learning matters: The role of learning in concept acquisition. Mind & Language, 26(5), 507–539.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newcombe, N. (2002). The nativist-empiricist controversy in the context of recent research on spatial and quantitative development. Psychological Science, 13, 395–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1954). The construction of reality in the child (M. Cook, Trans.). New York: Basic Books.

  • Pinker, S. (1997). How the mind works. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2002). Furnishing the mind: Concepts and their perceptual basis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1967). The ‘innateness hypothesis’ and explanatory models in linguistics. Synthese, 17, 12–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1976). Linguistics and philosophy. In W. V. O. Quine (ed.), The ways of paradox and other essays, revised. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Ratcliffe, J. M., Fenton, M. B., & Galef, B. G., Jr. (2003). An exception to the rule: Common vampire bats do not learn taste aversions. Animal Behaviour, 65, 385–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Regolin, L., & Vallortigara, G. (1995). Perception of partially occluded objects by young chicks. Perception & Psychophysics, 57, 971–976.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Revusky, S., & Garcia, J. (1970). Learned associations over long delays. In G. H. Bower & J. T. Spence (Eds.), The psychology of learning and motivation. New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rozin, P., & Kalat, J. (1971). Specific hungers and poison avoidance as adaptive specializations of learning. Psychological Review, 78, 459–486.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sampson, G. (2005). The ‘Language Instinct’ debate, revised. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Samuels, R. (2002). Nativism in cognitive science. Mind and Language, 17, 233–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scholz, B., & Pullum, G. K. (2006). Irrational nativist exuberance. In R. Stainton (Ed.), Contemporary debates in cognitive science. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1992). The rediscovery of the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shettleworth, S. (2009). Cognition, evolution, and behavior. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1957). Verbal behavior. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1999). Innate knowledge. In E. Sober (Ed.), The Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy (Vol. 4). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. (1975). The idea of innateness. In S. Stich (Ed.), Innate ideas. Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wehner, R., & Srinivasan, M. (1981). Searching behavior of desert ants, genus Cataglyphis (Formicidae, Hymenoptera). Journal of Comparative Physiology, 142, 315–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilcoxon, H. C., Dragoin, W. B., & Kral, P. A. (1971). Illness-induced aversions in rat and quail: Relative salience of visual and gustoatory cues. Science, 171, 826–828.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (1999). Generativity, entrenchment, evolution and innateness: Philosophy, evolutionary biology, and conceptual foundations of science. In V. Hardcastle (Ed.), Where biology meets psychology: Philosophical essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittlinger, M., Wehner, R., & Wolf, H. (2006). The ant odometer: Stepping on stilts and stumps. Science, 312, 1965–1967.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

EM would like to thank Canada’s Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council and the Peter Wall Institute for Advanced Studies for supporting this research.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eric Margolis.

Additional information

This article was fully collaborative; the order of the authors’ names is arbitrary.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Margolis, E., Laurence, S. In defense of nativism. Philos Stud 165, 693–718 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9972-x

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9972-x

Keywords

Navigation