Skip to main content
Log in

Social evolution and strategic thinking

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Thinking about organisms as if they were rational agents which could choose their own phenotypic traits according to their fitness values is a common heuristic in the field of evolutionary theory. In a 1998 paper, however, Elliott Sober has emphasized several alleged shortcomings of this kind of analogical reasoning when applied to the analysis of social behaviors. According to him, the main flaw of this heuristic is that it proves to be a misleading tool when it is used for predicting the evolution of cooperation. Here, I show that these charges raised against the heuristic use of this analogy are misguided. I argue, contra Sober, that such a heuristic turns out to be a perfect predictive tool in all relevant contexts where cooperation can at least evolve. Moreover, I argue that it constitutes a powerful and sufficient methodological framework for the analysis of social evolution.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I will not consider Sober’s objection to HP in the context of the iterated prisoner’s dilemma (the second in the order of Sober’s original exposition).

  2. There are in fact two necessary (and jointly sufficient) conditions for a game to be an n-player linear prisoner dilemma. First, the global welfare of a group must be strictly proportional to the number of cooperator in the group, or b > c. And second, each player must get a higher payoff in choosing to cooperate rather than to defect, or b/n < c.

  3. It is unsatisfiable in the limit of an infinite population, since c > 0 in such a case.

  4. When the population is randomly structured in groups of size n, the probability of having i altruists in a given group is binomial.

  5. More precisely, a trait will be considered as being weakly altruistic when it provides a net benefit x to the actor, and when the benefit y that is provided by the actor to the recipient is such that y > x.

  6. For a more extended discussion of Nunney’s argument and its relevance for the debates on multilevel selection, see Okasha (2006) and Godfrey-Smith (2008).

  7. Note that it doesn’t matter for my argument how precisely the groups are defined, neither how there are formed. As Nunney has himself showed in his 1985 paper, the HP works equally well in viscous populations where groups are not well defined by clear boundaries. But see Godfrey-Smith (2008) for a very good treatment of these problems raised in evolutionary theory by the varieties of possible population structures.

  8. As Sober remarks, there is nevertheless a special case when P(C/C) − P(C/D) = 0, in which the HP and the CARF method gives exactly the same prediction, i.e. that defection will evolve in the population.

  9. Interestingly, this difficulty was alluded to by Sober himself and led him to specify the conclusion of his objection: “If the dominance principle is correct, selfishness is the rational act. But why buy the dominance principle? It is in conflict with some formulations of decision theory, as aficionados of the Newcomb problem well realize. I will not try to track this argument back to first principles, so perhaps my conclusion should be more conditional: if the dominance principle is a correct rule for rational deliberation, then the one-shot Prisoner’s Dilemma provides a counter-example to the heuristic of personification” (Sober 1998, p. 411).

  10. In addition, one should note that we are not even bound to renounce to the dominance principle in adopting Jeffrey expected utility. In the second edition of The Logic of Decision (1983), Jeffrey has indeed amended his own model so that it could account for the dominance principle. This was done by the introduction of a new concept, that of “ratifiability”. Skyrms (1994) argues moreover that some variant of the concept of “ratifiability” is the appropriate generalization of that of “evolutionary stable strategy” (Maynard Smith 1982) in correlated evolutionary game theory. See Skyrms (1990) for further discussion of the concept of ratifiability and its significance in Jeffrey’s thought, and Skyrms (1994) for a discussion of this concept related to evolutionary game theory.

References

  • Bergstrom TC (2002) Evolution of social behavior: individual and group selection. J Econ Perspect 16(2):67–88

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1976) The selfish gene. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1982) The extended phenotype. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank SA (1994) Genetics of mutualism: the evolution of altruism between species. J Theor Biol 170:393–400

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank SA (1998) The foundations of social evolution. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank SA (2006) Social selection. In: Fox CW, Wolf JB (eds) Evolutionary genetics: concepts and case studies. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 350–363

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard A, Harper W (1981) Counterfactuals and two kinds of expected utility. In: Harper W, Stalnaker R, Pearce G (eds) IFS: conditionals, beliefs, decision, chance, and time. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 153–190

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2008) Varieties of population structure and the level of selection. Br J Philos Sci 59:25–50

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2009) Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Grafen A (1984) Natural selection, kin selection, and group selection. In: Krebs JR, Davies NB (eds) Behavioral ecology: an evolutionary approach. Sinauer, Sunderland, pp 62–84

    Google Scholar 

  • Grafen A (1985) A geometric view of relatedness. Oxford Surv Evol Biol 2:28–89

    Google Scholar 

  • Grafen A (1990) Do animals really recognize kin? Anim Behav 39:42–54

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grafen A (2002) A first formal link between the price equation and an optimization program. J Theor Biol 217:75–91

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grafen A (2006) Optimization of inclusive fitness. J Theor Biol 238:541–563

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grafen A (2007) The formal darwinism project: a mid-term report. J Evol Biol 20:1243–1254

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton WD (1964) The genetical evolution of social behaviour I, II. J Theor Biol 7(1–16):17–52

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey R (1983) The logic of decision, 2nd edn. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Kerr B, Godfrey-Smith P (2002) Individualist and multi-level perspectives on selection in structured populations. Biol Philos 17(4):477–517

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kreps DM (1988) Notes on the theory of choice. Westview Press, Boulder and Boldon

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (1981) Causal decision theory. Australas J Philos 58:5–30

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacArthur RH, Pianka ER (1966) On optimal use of a patchy environment. Am Nat 100:603–609

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J (1982) Evolution and the theory of games. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Michod R (1982) The theory of kin selection. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 13:23–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moran PAP (1964) On the nonexistence of adaptive topographies. Ann Hum Genet 27:383–393

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nunney L (1985) Group selection, altruism, and structured-deme models. Am Nat 126(4):212–230

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha S (2002) Genetic relatedness and the evolution of altruism. Philos Sci 69:138–149

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha S (2006) Evolution and the levels of selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Olson M (1965) The logic of collective action. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Queller DC, Strassmann JE (1998) Kin selection and social insects. Bioscience 48:165–174

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rapport DJ, Turner JE (1977) Economic models in ecology. Science 195:367–373

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Riolo RL, Cohen MD, Axelrod R (2001) Evolution of cooperation without reciprocity. Nature 414:441–443

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savage LJ (1954) The foundations of statistics. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms B (1990) Ratifiability and the logic of decision. In: French PA, Uehling TE Jr, Wettstein HK (eds) Midwest studies in philosophy vol 15, The philosophy of the human sciences, vol 15. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, pp 44–56

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms B (1994) Darwin meets the logic of decision: correlation in evolutionary game theory. Philos Sci 61:503–528

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1998) Three differences between evolution and deliberation. In: Danielson P (ed) Modeling rationality, morality and evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 408–422

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E, Wilson DS (1998) Unto others: the evolution and psychology of unselfish behavior. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • West SA, Griffin AS, Gardner A (2008) How useful has group selection been? J Evol Biol 22:374–385

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson DS (1975) A theory of group selection. PNAS 72(1):143–146

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson DS (1990) Weak altruism, strong group selection. Oikos 59(1):135–140

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson DS (1998) Hunting, sharing and multilevel selection: the tolerated theft model revisited. Curr Anthropol 39:73–97

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kerr B, Godfrey-Smith P, Feldman M (2004) What is altruism? Trends Ecol Evol 19(3):135–140

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson DS (2004a) What is wrong with absolute individual fitness? Trends Ecol Evol 19(5):245–248

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson DS (2004b) The new fable of the bees: multilevel selection, adaptive societies, and the concept of self interest. Adv Austrian Econ 7:201–220

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Philippe Huneman and Samir Okasha for their helpful comments on this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Johannes Martens.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Martens, J. Social evolution and strategic thinking. Biol Philos 26, 697–715 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-011-9276-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-011-9276-0

Keywords

Navigation